4. Marx’s Labour Theory of
Value
As an economist, Marx is
generally situated in the continuity of the great classical
school of Adam Smith and Ricardo. He obviously owes a lot to
Ricardo, and conducts a running dialogue with that master in
most of his mature economic writings.
Marx inherited the labour
theory of value from the classical school. Here the continuity
is even more pronounced; but there is also a radical break, For
Ricardo, labour is essentially a numeraire, which
enables a common computation of labour and capital as basic
elements of production costs. For Marx, labour is value.
Value is nothing but that fragment of the total labour potential
existing in a given society in a certain period (e.g. a year or
a month) which is used for the output of a given commodity, at
the average social productivity of labour existing then and
there, divided by the total number of these commodities
produced. and expressed in hours (or minutes), days, weeks,
months of labour.
Value is therefore essentially
a social, objective and historically relative category, It is
social because it is determined by the overall result of the
fluctuating efforts of each individual producer (under
capitalism: of each individual firm or factory). It is objective
because it is given, once the production of a given commodity is
finished, and is thus independent from personal (or collective)
valuations of customers on the market place; and it is
historically relative because it changes with each important
change (progress or regression) of the average productivity of
labour in a given branch of output, including in agriculture and
transportation.
This does not imply that
Marx’s concept of value is in any way completely detached from
consumption. It only means that the feedback of consumers’
behaviour and wishes upon value is always mediated through
changes in the allocation of labour inputs in production, labour
being seen as subdivided into living labour and dead (dated)
labour, i.e. tools and raw materials. The market emits signals
to which the producing units react. Value changes after these
reactions, not before them. Market price changes can of course
occur prior to changes in value. In fact, changes in market
prices are among the key signals which can lead to changes in
labour allocation between different branches of production, i.e.
to changes in labour quantities necessary to produce given
commodities. But then, for Marx, values determine prices only
basically and in the medium-term sense of the word. This
determination only appears clearly as an explication of medium
and long-term price movements. In the shorter run, prices
fluctuate around values as axes. Marx never intended to negate
the operation of market laws, of the law of supply and demand,
in determining these short-term fluctuations.
The ‘law of value’ is but
Marx’s version of Adam Smith’s ‘invisible hand’. In a
society dominated by private labour, private producers and
private ownership of productive inputs, it is this ‘law of
value’, an objective economic law operating behind the backs
of all people, all ‘agents’ involved in production and
consumption, which, in the final analysis, regulates the
economy, determines what is produced and how it is produced (and
therefore also what can be consumed). The ‘law of value’
regulates the exchange between commodities, according to the
quantities of socially necessary abstract labour they embody
(the quantity of such labour spent in their production). Through
regulating the exchange between commodities, the ‘law of
value’ also regulates, after some interval, the distribution
of society’s labour potential and of society’s non-living
productive resources between different branches of production.
Again, the analogy with Smith’s ‘invisible hand’ is
striking.
Marx’s critique of the
‘invisible hand’ concept does not dwell essentially on the
analysis of how a market economy actually operates. It would
above all insist that this operation is not eternal, not
immanent in ‘human nature’, but created by specific
historical circumstances, a product of a special way of social
organisation, and due to disappear at some stage of historical
evolution as it appeared during a previous stage. And it would
also stress that this ‘invisible hand’ leads neither to the
maximum of economic growth nor to the optimum of human wellbeing
for the greatest number of individuals, i.e. it would stress the
heavy economic and social price humankind had to pay, and is
still currently paying, for the undeniable progress the market
economy produced at a given stage of historical evolution.
The formula ‘quantities of
abstract human labour’ refers to labour seen strictly as a
fraction of the total labour potential of a given society at a
given time, say a labour potential of 2 billion hours a year (1
million potential producers, each supposedly capable of working
2000 hours a year). It therefore implies making an abstraction
of the specific trade or occupation of a given male or female
producer, the product of a day’s work of a weaver not being
worth less or more than that of a peasant, a miner, a
house-builder, a milliner or a seamstress. At the basis of that
concept of ‘abstract human labour’ lies a social condition,
a specific set of social relations of production, in which small
independent producers are essentially equal. Without that
equality, social division of labour, and therefore satisfaction
of basic consumers’ needs, would be seriously endangered under
that specific organisational set-up of the economy. Such an
equality between small commodity owners and producers is later
transformed into an equality between owners of capital under the
capitalist mode of production.
But the concept of the
homogeneity of productive human labour, underlying that of
‘abstract human labour’ as the essence of value, does not
imply a negation of the difference between skilled and unskilled
labour. Again: a negation of that difference would lead to the
breakdown of the necessary division of labour, as would any
basic heterogeneity of labour inputs in different branches of
output. It would then not pay to acquire skills: most of them
would disappear. So Marx’s labour theory of value, in an
internally coherent way, leads to the conclusion that one hour
of skilled labour represents more value than one hour of
unskilled labour, say represents the equivalent of 1.5 hours of
unskilled labour. The difference would result from the
imputation of the labour it costs to acquire the given skill,
While an unskilled labourer would have a labour potential of
120,000 hours during his adult life, a skilled labourer would
only have a labour potential of 80,000 hours, 40,000 being used
for acquiring, maintaining and developing his skill. Only if one
hour of skilled labour embodies the same value of 1.5 hours of
unskilled labour, will the equality of all ‘economic agents’
be maintained under these circumstances, i.e. will it ‘pay’
economically to acquire a skill.
Marx himself never extensively
dwelled on this solution of the so-called reduction problem.
This remains indeed one of the most obscure parts of his general
economic theory. It has led to some, generally rather mild,
controversy. Much more heat has been generated by another facet
of Marx’s labour theory of value, the so-called transformation
problem. Indeed, from Böhm-Bawerk writing a century ago
till the recent contributions of Sraffa (1960) and Steedman
(1977), the way Marx dealt with the transformation of values
into ‘prices of production’ in Capital Vol.
III has been considered by many of his critics as the main
problem of his ‘system’, as well as being a reason to reject
the labour theory of value out of hand.
The problem arises out of the
obvious modification in the functioning of a market economy when
capitalist commodity production substitutes itself for simple
commodity production. In simple commodity production, with
generally stable technology and stable (or easily reproducible)
tools, living labour is the only variable of the quantity and
subdivision of social production. The mobility of labour is the
only dynamic factor in the economy. As Engels pointed out in his
Addendum to Capital Vol. III (Marx, g, pp,
1034-7), in such an economy, commodities would be exchanged at
prices which would be immediately proportional to values, to the
labour inputs they embody.
But under the capitalist mode
of production, this is no longer the case. Economic
decision-taking is not in the hands of the direct producers. It
is in the hands of the capitalist entrepreneurs in the
wider sense of the word (bankers – distributors of credit –
playing a key role in that decision-taking, besides
entrepreneurs in the productive sector properly speaking).
Investment decisions, i.e. decisions for creating, expanding,
reducing or closing enterprises, determine economic life. It is
the mobility of capital and not the mobility of labour
which becomes the motive force of the economy. Mobility of
labour becomes essentially an epiphenomenon of the mobility of
capital.
Capitalist production is
production for profit. Mobility of capital is determined by
existing or expected profit differentials. Capital leaves
branches (countries, regions) with lower profits (or profit
expectations) and flows towards branches (countries, regions)
with higher ones. These movements lead to an equalisation of the
rate of profit between different branches of production. But
approximately equal returns on all invested capital (at least
under conditions of prevailing ‘free competition’) coexist
with unequal proportions of inputs of labour in these different
branches. So there is a disparity between the direct value of a
commodity and its ‘price of production’, that ‘price of
production’ being defined by Marx as the sum of production
costs (costs of fixed capital and raw materials plus wages) and
the average rate of profit multiplied with the capital spent in
the given production.
The so-called ‘transformation
problem’ relates to the question of whether a relation
can nevertheless be established between value and these
‘prices of production’, what is the degree of coherence (or
incoherence) of the relation with the ‘law of value’ (the
labour theory of value in general), and what is the correct
quantitative way to express that relation, if it exists.
We shall leave aside here the
last aspect of the problem, to which extensive analysis has
recently been devoted (Mandel and Freeman, 1984). From Marx’s
point of view, there is no incoherence between the formation of
‘prices of production’ and the labour theory of value. Nor
is it true that he came upon that alleged difficulty when he
started to prepare Capital Vol.III, i.e. to
deal with capitalist competition, as several critics have argued
(see e.g. Joan Robinson, 1942). In fact, his solution of the
transformation problem is already present in the Grundrisse,
before he even started to draft Capital Vol. I.
The sum total of value produced
in a given country during a given span of time (e.g. one year)
is determined by the sum total of labour-inputs. Competition and
movements of capital cannot change that quantity, The sum total
of values equals the sum total of ‘prices of production’.
The only effect of capital competition and capital mobility is
to redistribute that given sum – and this through a
redistribution of surplus value (see below) – between
different capitals, to the benefit of some and at the expense of
others.
Now the redistribution does not
occur in a haphazard or arbitrary way. Essentially value
(surplus-value) is transferred from technically less advanced
branches to technologically more advanced branches. And here the
concept of ‘quantities of socially necessary labour’ comes
into its own, under the conditions of constant revolutions of
productive technology that characterise the capital mode of
production. Branches with lower than average technology (organic
composition of capital, see below) can be considered as wasting
socially necessary labour. Part of the labour spent in
production in their realm is therefore not compensated by
society. Branches with higher than average technology (organic
composition of capital) can be considered to be economising
social labour; their labour inputs can therefore be considered
as more intensive than average, embodying more value. In this
way, the transfer of value (surplus-value) between different
branches, far from being in contradiction with the law of value,
is precisely the way it operates and should operate under
conditions of ‘capitalist equality’, given the pressure of
rapid technological change.
As to the logical inconsistency
often supposedly to be found in Marx’s method of solving the
‘transformation problem’ – first advanced by von
Bortkiewicz (1907) – it is based upon a misunderstanding in
our opinion. It is alleged that in his ‘transformation
schemas’ (or tables) Marx calculates inputs in ‘values’
and outputs in ‘prices of production’, thereby omitting the
feedback effect of the latter on the former. But that feedback
eject is unrealistic and unnecessary, once one recognises that
inputs are essentially data. Movements of capital posterior to
the purchase of machinery or raw materials, including the ups
and dawns of prices of finished products produced with these raw
materials, cannot lead to a change in prices and therefore of
profits of the said machinery and raw materials, on sales which
have already occurred. What critics present as an inconsistency
between ‘values’ and ‘prices of production’ is simply a
recognition of two different time-frameworks (cycles)
in which the equalisation of the rate of profit has been
achieved, a first one for inputs, and a second, later one for
outputs.
|