3.
Marx’s Economic Theory – General approach and influence
A general appraisal of Marx’s
method of economic analysis is called for prior to an outline of
his main economic theories (theses and hypotheses). Marx is
distinct from most important economists of the 19th and 20th
centuries in that he does not consider himself at all an
‘economist’ pure and simple. The idea that ‘economic
science’ as a special science completely separate from
sociology, history, anthropology etc. cannot exist, underlies
most of his economic analysis. Indeed, historical materialism is
an attempt at unifying all social sciences, if not all sciences
about humankind, into a single ‘science of society’. For
sure, within the framework of this general ‘science of
society’, economic phenomena could and should be submitted to
analysis as specific phenomena. So economic theory, economical
science, has a definite autonomy after all; but it is only a
partial and relative one.
Probably the best formula for
characterising Marx’s economic theory would be to call it an
endeavour to explain the social economy. This would be
true in a double sense. For Marx, there are no eternal economic
laws, valid in every epoch of human prehistory and history. Each
mode of production has its own specific economic laws, which
lose their relevance once the general social framework has
fundamentally changed. For Marx likewise, there are no economic
laws separate and apart from specific relations between human
beings, in the primary (but not only, as already summarised)
social relations of production. All attempts to reduce economic
problems to purely material, objective ones, to relations
between things, or between things and human beings, would be
considered by Marx as manifestations of mystification, of false
consciousness, expressing itself through the attempted
relocation of human relations. Behind relations between things,
economic science should try to discover the specific relations
between human beings which they hide. Real economic science has
therefore also a demystifying function compared to vulgar
‘economics’, which takes a certain number of ‘things’
for granted without asking the questions: Are they really only
what they appear to be? From where do they originate? What
explains these appearances? What lies behind them? Where do they
lead? How could they (will they) disappear? Problemblindheit,
the refusal to see that facts are generally more problematic
than they appear at first sight, is certainly not a reproach one
could address to Marx’s economic thought.
Marx’s economic analysis is
therefore characterised by a strong ground current of historical
relativism, with a strong recourse to the genetical and
evolutionary method of thinking (that is why the parallel with
Darwin has often been made, sometimes in an excessive way). The
formula ‘genetic structuralism’ has also been used in
relation to Marx’s general approach to economic analysis. Be
that as it may, one could state that Marx’s economic theory is
essentially geared to the discovery of specific ‘laws of
motion’ for successive modes of production. While his
theoretical effort has been mainly centred around the discovery
of these laws of motion for capitalist society, his work
contains indications of such laws – different ones, to be sure
– for pre-capitalist and post-capitalist social formations
too.
The main link between Marx’s
sociology and anthropology on the one hand, and his economic
analysis on the other, lies in the key role of social labour
as the basic anthropological feature underlying all forms of
social organisation. Social labour can be organised in quite
different forms, thereby giving rise to quite different economic
phenomena (‘facts’). Basically different forms of social
labour organisation lead to basically different sets of economic
institutions and dynamics, following basically different logics
(obeying basically different ‘laws of motion’).
All human societies must assure
the satisfaction of a certain number of basic needs, in order to
survive and reproduce themselves. This leads to the necessity of
establishing some sort of equilibrium between social recognised
needs, i.e. current consumption and current production. But this
abstract banality does not tell us anything about the concrete
way in which social labour is organised in order to achieve that
goal.
Society can recognise all
individual labour as immediately social labour. Indeed,
it does so in innumerable primitive tribal and village
communities, as it does in the contemporary kibbutz.
Directly social labour can be organised in a despotic or in a
democratic way, through custom and superstition as well as
through an attempt at applying advanced science to economic
organisation; but it will always be immediately recognised
social labour, inasmuch as it is based upon a priori
assignment of the producers to their specific work (again:
irrespective of the form this assignation takes, whether it is
voluntary or compulsory, despotic or simply through custom
etc.).
But when social decision-taking
about work assignation (and resource allocation closely tied to
it) is fragmented into different units operating independently
from each other – as a result of private control (property) of
the means of production, in the economic and not necessarily the
juridical sense of the word – then social labour in turn is
fragmented into private labours which are not automatically
recognised as socially necessary ones (whose expenditure is not
automatically compensated by society). Then the private
producers have to exchange parts or all of their products in
order to satisfy some or all of their basic needs. Then these
products become commodities, The economy becomes a (partial or
generalised) market economy. Only by measuring the results of
the sale of his products can the producer (or owner) ascertain
what part of his private labour expenditure has been recognized
(compensated) as social labour, and what part has not.
Even if we operate with such
simple analytical tools as ‘directly social labour’,
‘private labour’, ‘socially recognised social labour’,
we have to make quite an effort at abstracting from immediately
apparent phenomena in order to understand their relevance for
economic analysis. This is true for all scientific analysis, in
natural as well as in social sciences. Marx’s economic
analysis, as presented in his main books, has not been extremely
popular reading; but then, there are not yet so many scientists
in these circumstances. This has nothing to do with any innate
obscurity of the author, but rather with the nature of
scientific analysis as such.
The relatively limited number
of readers of Marx’s economic writings (the first English
paperback edition of Das Kapital appeared only
in 1974!) is clearly tied to Marx’s scientific rigour, his
effort at a systematic and all-sided analysis of the phenomena
of the capitalist economy.
But while his economic analysis
lacked popularity, his political and historical projections
became more and more influential. With the rise of independent
working-class mass parties, an increasing number of these
proclaimed themselves as being guided or influenced by Marx, at
least in the epoch of the Second and the Third Internationals,
roughly the half century from 1890 till 1940. Beginning with the
Russian revolution of 1917, a growing number of governments and
of states claimed to base their policies and constitutions on
concepts developed by Marx. (Whether this was legitimate or not
is another question.) But the fact itself testifies to Marx’s
great influence on contemporary social and political
developments, evolutionary and revolutionary alike.
Likewise, his diffused
influence on social science, including academic economic theory,
goes far beyond general acceptance or even substantial knowledge
of his main writings. Some key ideas of historical materialism
and of economic analysis which permeate his work – e.g. that
economic interests to a large extent influence, if not
determine, political struggles; that historic evolution is
linked to important changes in material conditions; that
economic crises (‘the business cycle’) are unavoidable under
conditions of capitalist market economy – have become
near-platitudes. It is sufficient to notice how major economists
and historians strongly denied their validity throughout the
19th century and at least until the 1920s, to understand how
deep has been Marx’s influence on contemporary social science
in general.
|