I. What Is A
Revolution?
Revolutions are historical
facts of life. Almost all major states in today's world are born
from revolutions. Whether one likes it or not, our century has
seen something like three dozen revolutions – some victorious,
others defeated – and there is no sign that we have come to
the end of the revolutionary experience.
Revolutions have been, and will
remain, facts of life because of the structural nature of
prevailing relations of production and relations of political
power. Precisely because such relations are structural, because
they do not just “fade away” – as well as because ruling
classes resist the gradual elimination of these relations to the
very end – revolutions emerge as the means whereby the
overthrow of these relations is realized.
From the nature of revolutions
as a sudden, radical overthrow of prevailing social and (or)
political structures – leaps in the historical process – one
should not draw the conclusion that an impenetrable Chinese wall
separates evolution (or reforms) from revolution. Quantitative
gradual social changes of course do occur in history, as do
qualitative revolutionary ones. Very often the former prepare
the latter especially in epochs of decay of a given mode of
production. Prevailing economic and political power relations
can be eroded, undermined, increasingly challenged or can even
be slowly disintegrated, by new relations of production and the
political strength of revolutionary classes (or major class
fractions) rising in their midst. This is what generally
characterizes periods of pre-revolutionary crises. But erosion
and decay of a given social and/or political order remains
basically different from its overthrow. Evolution is not
identical with revolution. One transforms dialectics into
sophism when, from the fact that there is no rigid absolute
distinction between evolution and revolution, one draws the
conclusion that there is no basic difference between them at
all.
The sudden overthrow of ruling
structures is, however, only one key characteristic of that
social phenomenon. The other one is their overthrow through huge
popular mobilization, through the sudden massive active
intervention of large masses of ordinary people in political
life and political struggle. [1]
One of the great mysteries of
class society, based upon exploitation and oppression of the
mass of direct producers by relatively small minorities, is why
that mass in “normal” times by and large tolerates these
conditions, be it with all kinds of periodic but limited
reactions. Historical materialism tries, not without success, to
explain that mystery. The explanation is many-dimensional,
drawing upon a combination of economic compulsion, ideological
manipulation, cultural socialization, political-juridical
repression (including occasionally violence), psychological
processes (interiorization, identification), etc.
Generally, as one revolutionary
newspaper wrote at the beginning of the French revolution of
1789, oppressed people feel weak before their oppressors in
spite of their numerical superiority, because they are on their
knees. [2] A revolution can
occur precisely when that feeling of weakness and helplessness
is overcome, when the mass of the people suddenly thinks “We
don't take it any longer,” and acts accordingly. In his
interesting book, The Social Bases of Obedience and
Revolt, Barrington Moore has tried to prove that
suffering and consciousness of injustice are not sufficient to
induce large-scale revolts (revolutions) in broader masses. In
his opinion, a decisive role is played by the conviction that
suffered injustice is neither inevitable nor a “lesser
evil,” i.e. that a better social set-up could be realized. [3]
A concomitant brake upon direct challenges to a given social
and/or political order, however, is the locally or regionally
fragmented nature of revolts pure and simple. Revolts generally
become revolutions when they are unified nation-wide.
Such challenges can be
explained, among other things, by that basic truth about class
societies formulated by Abraham Lincoln, empirically confirmed
throughout history, and which is at least one reason for
historical optimism (belief in the possibility of human
progress) when all is said and done: “You can fool all of the
people some of the time and some of the people all of the time.
But you can’t fool all of the people all of the time.”
When the majority of the people
refuse to be fooled and intimidated any longer; when they refuse
to stay on their knees; when they recognize the fundamental
weakness of their oppressors, they can become transformed
overnight from seemingly meek, subdued and helpless sheep into
mighty lions. They strike, congregate, organize and especially
demonstrate in the streets in increasing numbers, even in the
face of massive, gruesome, bloody repression by the rulers, who
still have a powerful armed apparatus at their disposal. They
often show unheard of forms of heroism, self-sacrifice,
obstinate endurance. [4]
This may end in their getting the better of the repressive
apparatus which starts to disintegrate. The first victory of
every revolution is precisely such a disintegration. Its final
victory calls for the substitution of the armed power of the
revolutionary class (or of a major class fraction) to that of
the former rulers. [5] Such
a descriptive definition of revolutions has to be integrated
into an analytical-casual one. Social revolutions occur when
prevailing relations of production cannot contain any more the
development of the productive forces, when they increasingly act
as fetters upon them, when they cause a cancerous growth of
destructiveness accompanying that development. Political
revolutions occur when prevailing relations of political power
(forms of state power) have likewise become fetters upon a
further development of the productive forces within the
framework of the prevailing relations of production, a
development which is however still historically possible. That
is why they generally consolidate a given social order, instead
of undermining it.
This materialist explanation of
revolutions offered by Marxism seems indispensable for answering
the question: “why, and why just at the moment?” Revolutions
have occurred in all types of class societies but not in a
uniform way. It appears clearly illogical to attribute them
either to permanently operating psychological factors
(humanity’s allegedly inborn aggression,
“destructiveness,” “envy,” “greed” or
“stupidity”) or to accidental quirks of the political power
structure: particularly inept, stupid, blind rulers, meeting
increasingly self-confident and active opponents. According to
the particular school of history concerned, one can see that
blind ineptitude either in the excessive recourse to repression,
or in the excessive amplitude of suddenly introduced reforms, or
in a peculiar explosive combination of both. [6]
There are of course kernels of
partial truth in such psychological and political analyses. But
they cannot explain in a satisfying way the regular and
discontinuous occurrence of revolutions, their cyclical nature
so to speak. Why do “inept” rulers at regular intervals
succeed “adequate” ones, so many times in so many countries?
This can surely not be caused by some mysterious genetical
mutation cycle. The big advantage of the materialist
interpretation of history is to explain that occurrence by
deeper socio-economic causes. It is not the ineptness of the
rulers which produces the pre-revolutionary crisis. It is the
paralysis engendered by an underlying social-structural crisis
which makes rulers increasingly inept. In that sense Trotsky was
absolutely right when he stressed that “revolutions are
nothing but the final blow and coup de grâce given to a
paralytic.”
Lenin summarized the underlying
analysis in a classical way by stating that revolutions occur
when those below do not accept any longer as before. The
inability of a ruling class or major fractions to continue to
rule has basically objective causes. These reflect themselves in
increasingly paralyzing internal divisions among the rulers,
especially around the question about how to get out of the mess
visible to the naked eye. It intertwines with growing
self-doubt, a loss of faith in its own future, an irrational
search for peculiar culprits (“conspiracy theories”)
substituting for a realistic objective analysis of social
contradictions. It is this combination which precisely produces
political ineptitude and counterproductive actions and
reactions, if not sheer passivity. The basic cause always
remains the rotting away of the system, not the peculiar
psychology of a group of rulers.
One has obviously to
distinguish the basic historical causes of revolutions from the
factors (events) triggering them off. The first ones are
structural, the second ones conjunctural. [7]
But it is important to emphasize that even as regards the
structural causes, the Marxist explication of revolutions is by
no means monocausally “economistic.” The conflict between
the productive forces and the prevailing relations of production
and/or political power relations isn’t all purely economic. It
is basically socio-economic. It involves all main spheres of
social relations. It even eventually finds its concentrated
expression in the political and not in the economic sphere. The
refusal of soldiers to shoot at demonstrators is a
political-moral and not an economic act. It is only by digging
farther below the surface of that refusal that one discovers its
material roots. These roots don’t transform the
political-moral decision into a pure “appearance,” or a
manifestation of mere shadow boxing. It has a clear reality of
its own. But that substantial reality in its turn doesn’t make
the digging for the deeper material roots irrelevant, an
exercise in “dogmatism” or an “abstract” analysis of
only secondary interest. [8]
In any case, the inability of
the rulers to continue to rule is not only a socio-political
fact, with its inevitable concomitant of an ideological
moral-crisis (a crisis of the prevailing “social values
system”). It has also a precise technical-material aspect. To
rule also means to control a material network of communications
and a centralized repressive apparatus. When that network breaks
down, the rule collapses in the immediate sense of the word. [9]
We must never, therefore, underestimate the technical aspect of
successful revolutions. But the Marxist theory of revolution
also supersedes a peculiar variant of the conspiracy theory of
history, which tends to substitute for an explanation of
victorious revolutions an exclusive reference to the technical
mechanism of successful insurrections or coups d’état. [10]
Instead, it is the material interests of key social forces and
their self-perception which provide the basic explanation of
turning points of history.
II.
Revolutions and Counter-revolutions
While revolutions are
historical facts of life, counter-revolutions are likewise
undeniable realities. Indeed, counter-revolutions seem regularly
to follow revolutions as night follows day. Etymology confirms
this paradox. The very concept of “revolution” originates
from the sciences of astronomy. The movements of planets evolve
in an orbital manner, returning to the point of departure. Hence
the suggested analogical conclusion: the role of revolutions as
great accelerators, as locomotives of history, is just an
optical illusion of short-sighted and superficial observers, not
to say utopian day-dreamers. It is precisely such an
interpretation (denigration) of revolutions which is compatible
with the great Italian historian Vico’s cyclical conception of
world history.
Under the influence of the
victorious counter-revolution in England in 1660, the great
political philosophers of the 17th century, above all Hobbes and
Spinoza, developed a basically pessimistic view of human
destiny. Revolutions are doomed to fail: “Plus ça change,
plus ça reste la même chose.” Two thousand years
earlier, Greek and Chinese political philosophers had arrived at
similar conclusions. There is supposedly no way out for human
destiny but the search for individual happiness under inevitably
bad social conditions, be it happiness through self-discipline
(Stoics, Confucians, Spinoza) or through hedonism (the
Epicureans). [11]
In the 18th century, the
Enlightenment questioned both the empirical and the theoretical
roots of dogmatic skeptical pessimism. [12]
The belief in the perfectibility of humankind (only sophists or
dishonest critics identify perfectibility with actually
attaining a final state of perfection, be it said in passing),
in historical progress, and thus likewise in the progressive
turns of revolutions, re-emerged. Revolution indeed looked
beautiful in times of reaction. But already before the outbreak
of the revolution of 1789, the camp of the Englightenment had
split between the basically skeptical and socially cautious, if
not outright conservative, bourgeois like Voltaire (“cultivez
votre jardin”) [13]
and the more radical petty-bourgeois ideologues like J.J.
Rousseau, who would inspire the Jacobin revolutionists. This
split deepened in the course of the revolution itself. After the
successive stages of counter-revolution (Thermidor, the
Bonapartist Consulate, the Empire, the Bourbon restoration) the
reversal to 17th century skepticism became general including
erstwhile enthusiasts for revolution, exemplified by the English
poet Wordsworth (but not Shelley). Only a tiny minority
continued to pin their hopes on future revolutions and to work
for them. [14] The
near-consensus was: the overhead of revolution is too large,
especially given the fact that they achieve very little. [15]
The Russian revolution’s
Thermidor and its tragic aftermath, the horrors of Stalinism,
reproduced the same revulsion towards revolutions, first in the
late nineteen-thirties and the forties, then, after a temporary
reprieve in the sixties and the early seventies, on a
generalized scale from the middle seventies on. The Soviet
military intervention in Czechoslovakia and especially Cambodia
and Afghanistan, but more generally the reflux of the
revolutionary wave 1968-1975 in Europe, from France through
Czechoslovakia, Italy, Portugal, strengthened this political
retreat. The near-consensus can again be summarized in the
formula: revolutions are both useless and harmful from every
point of view, including that of progress towards a more humane
society. Indeed, this is one of the key platitudes of today’s
prevailing neo-conservative, neo-liberal and neo-reformist
ideologies.
It is, however, based upon
obvious half-truths, if not outright mystifications. The idea
that revolutions revert to these historical points of departure,
if not to situations worse than the pre-revolutionary ones, is
generally based upon a confusion between social and political
counter-revolutions. While a few social counter-revolutions have
indeed occurred, they are the exception, not the rule. Neither
Napoleon nor Louis XVIII restored semi-feudal socio-economic
conditions in the French countryside, nor the political rule of
the semi-feudal nobility. Stalin did not restore capitalism in
Russia, nor did Deng Xiaoping in China. [16]
The restoration in England was quickly followed by the Glorious
Revolution. The compromise of the American constitution did not
lead eventually to the generalization of slave labor but to its
suppression, after the civil war. The list can be extended ad
libitum.
To this objective
balance-sheet, the problems of subjective choice are closely
related. They confront the skeptics and the pessimists with a
real dilemma. Counter-revolutions are not simply “natural”
reactions to revolutions, the product of an inevitable
mechanical yo-yo movement so to speak. They originate from the
same exacerbation of a system’s inner contradictions which
give rise to the revolution, but with a specific shift in
socio-political relations of forces. They reflect the relative
decline of political mass activity and efficiency. There is
indeed a “natural law” operating here. As genuine popular
revolutions generally imply a qualitatively increased level of
political mass activity, this cannot be sustained indefinitely,
for obvious material and psychological reasons. You have to
produce in order to eat, and when you demonstrate and
participate in mass meetings, you don’t produce. Also, great
masses of people cannot live permanently at a high level of
excitement and expenditure of nervous energy. [17]
To this relative decline in
mass activity corresponds a relative rise of activity and
efficiency of the old ruling classes or strata and their various
supporters and hangers-on. The initiative shifts from the
“left” to the “right,” at least momentarily (and not
necessarily with total success: there have been defeated
counter-revolutions as there have been defeated revolutions). [18]
There are likewise preventive counter-revolutions: Indonesia
1965 and Chile 1973 may be taken as examples. But precisely
these preventive counter-revolutions clearly reveal the
pessimistic skeptic’s dilemma. They are generally very costly
in terms of human lives and human happiness – much more costly
than revolutions. It stands to reason that much more repression,
much more bloodletting, much more cruelty, including torture, is
needed to suppress a highly active, broad mass of ordinary
people than to neutralize a small group of rulers. So by
abstaining from active intervention against a rising
counter-revolution – on the pretext that revolution itself is
useless and bad – one actually becomes a passive if not active
accomplice of bloody counter-revolution and large-scale mass
suffering.
This is morally revolting, as
it means tolerating, aiding and abetting the violence and
exploitation of the oppressors, while finding all kinds of
rationalizations for refusing to assist the oppressed in their
self-defence and attempted emancipation. And it is political
counter-productive as well as obnoxious. In the end, it often
proves to be suicidal from the point of view of the skeptics’
alleged devotion to the defence of democratic institutions and
reforms. The most tragic example in that respect was that of
German social-democracy at the end of World War One. Under the
alleged motive of “saving democracy”, Ebert and Noske kept
the Imperial army’s hierarchy and the Prussian officers’
corps intact. They conspired with it against the workers –
first in Berlin itself, then in the whole country. They made the
generals of the Reichswehr into the political arbiters of the
Weimar Republic. They permitted them to create and consolidate
the Freikorps from which a good part of the later SA and SS
cadres were recruited. They thereby paved the way of the rise
and eventual conquest of power by the Nazis, which in turn led
to the social-democrats’ destruction. They thought they could
contain regression and reaction in the framework of a democratic
counter-revolution. [19]
History taught the bitter lesson that democratic
counter-revolutions in the end often lead to much more
authoritarian and violent ones, when the sharpening of the
socio-economic contradictions makes a total instead of a partial
suppression of the mass movement into an immediate goal of the
ruling class.
This again is not accidental
but corresponds to a deeper historical logic. The essence of
revolution is often identified with a widespread explosion of
violence and mass killings. This is of course not true. The
essence of revolution is not the use of violence in politics but
a radical, qualitative challenge – and eventually the
overthrow – of prevailing economic or political power
structures. The larger the number of people involved in mass
actions targeting these structures, the more favorable the
relationship of forces between revolutions and reaction, the
greater the self-confidence of the first and the
moral-ideological paralysis of the second, and the less the
masses are inclined to use violence. Indeed, widespread use of
violence is counter-productive for the revolution at that
precise phase of the historical process.
But what does occur most often,
if not always, at some point of the revolutionary process, is
the desperate recourse to violence by the most radical and the
most resolute sectors of the rulers’ camp, intent on risking
everything before it is too late, because they still have human
and material resources left to act in that way. At some
culminating point, the confrontation between revolution and
counter-revolution thus generally does assume a violent
character, although the degree of violence largely depends upon
the overall relationship of forces. In answer to reaction’s
violence, the masses will tend towards armed self-defence.
Disintegration, paralysis and disarming of the
counter-revolution paves the way towards revolutionary victory.
Victory of counter-revolution depends upon disarming the mass. [20]
When the chips are down, when
power relations are stripped of all mediations and are nakedly
reduced to bare essentials, Friedrich Engels’ formula is then
borne out by empirical evidence: in the final analysis, the
state is indeed a gang of armed people. The class or layer which
has the monopoly of armed force possesses (either keeps or
conquers) state power. And that again is what revolution, and
counter-revolution, are all about. Sitting on the sidelines
cannot prevent this confrontation. Nor can it contribute to
delaying for ever the day of reckoning. In the last analysis the
skeptics’ and reformists’ revulsion from revolution covers
an implicit choice: the conservation of the status quo is at
best a lesser evil compared to the costs and consequences of its
revolutionary overthrow. This choice reflects social
conservatism, not a rational judgment of empirically verifiable
balance-sheets of “costs” of historical, i.e. real,
revolutions and counter-revolutions.
No normal human being prefers
to achieve social goals through the use of violence. To reduce
violence to the utmost in political life should be a common
endeavor for all progressive and socialist currents. Only
profoundly sick persons – totally unable to contribute to the
building of a real classless society – can actually enjoy
advocating and practicing violence on a significant scale.
Indeed, the increasing rejection of violence in a growing number
of countries is a clear indicator that at least some
moral-ideological progress has occurred in the last 70-75 years.
One has just to compare the wild and brazen justification of war
by nearly all the leading Western intellectuals and politicians
in the 1914-1918 period to the near universal revulsion towards
war today in the same milieu to note that progress.
Double moral standards still
reign supreme in inter-class and inter-state relations, but the
legitimacy of widespread use of violence by the rulers is at
least increasingly questioned in a systematic and consistent way
by a much greater number of people than in 1914-1918 or
1939-1945. The future, indeed the very physical survival of
humankind, depends upon the outcome of this race between
increasing consciousness about the necessary rejection of armed
confrontation on the one hand, and increasing de facto
destructiveness of existing and future weapons on the other. If
the first does not eliminate the second through successful
political action, the second will eventually destroy not only
the first but all human life on earth.
But such a political action can
only be revolutionary and thus implies the use of at least
limited armed force. To believe otherwise is to believe that the
rulers will let themselves be disarmed utterly peacefully,
without using the arms they still control. This is to deny the
threat of any violent counter-revolution, which is utterly
utopian in the light of actual historical experience. It is to
assume that ruling classes and strata are exclusively and always
represented by mild well-meaning liberals. Go tell that to the
prisoners of the Warsaw ghetto and of Auschwitz, to the million
victims of Djakarta, to the oppressed non-white population of
South Africa, to the Indochinese peoples, to the Chilean and
Salvadoran workers and peasants, to the murdered participants of
the Intifada, to the millions and millions of victims of
reaction and counter-revolution throughout the world since the
colonial wars of the 19th century and the Paris Commune. The
elementary human moral duty in the face of that terrifying
record is to refuse any retreat into (re)privatization and to
assist by any means necessary the oppressed, the exploited, the
humiliated, the downtrodden, to struggle for their emancipation.
In the long run, this makes also the individual participant a
more human, i.e. happier person, provided he does not make any
pseudo-Real political concessions and observes unrestrictedly
the rule: fight everywhere and always against any and every
social and political condition which exploits and oppresses
human beings.
III. The
Possibility of Revolution in the West
Revolutions and
counter-revolutions, being real historical processes, always
occur in really existing social-economic formations which are
always specific. No two countries in the world are exactly
alike, if only because their basic social classes and the major
fractions of these classes are products of the specific history
of each of these countries. Hence the character of each
revolution reflects a unique combination of the general and the
specific. The first derives from the logic of revolutions as
sketched before. The second derives from the specificity of each
particular set of prevailing relations of production and
relations of political power in a given country, at a given
moment, with its specific inner contradictions and a specific
dynamic of their exacerbation.
A revolutionary strategy [21]
represents the conscious attempt by revolutionists to influence
by their political actions the outcome of objectively
revolutionary processes in favor of a victory of the exploited
and the oppressed, in today’s world essentially the
wage-earning proletariat, its allies and the poor peasantry. It
has therefore in turn to be specific to have a minimum chance of
success. This means that it has to be attuned to the
differentiated social reality which prevails in today’s world.
We can use the formula of the “three sectors of world
revolution” to designate significantly different strategic
tasks, that is, roughly: the proletarian revolution in the
imperialist countries; the combined national-democratic,
anti-imperialist and socialist revolution in the so-called
“third world countries”; the political revolution in the
post-capitalist social formations. [22]
We shall consider each of these in turn.
Regarding the industrialized
metropolises of capitalism, a formidable objection is raised
with regard to the possible effectiveness of revolutionary
strategy. Many skeptics and reformists do not limit themselves
to allege that revolutions are useless and harmful. They add
that revolutions are impossible in these countries, that they
won’t occur anyway, that to hope for them or expect them is
utterly utopian; that to try to prepare for them or to further
them is a total waste of time and energy.
This line of reasoning is based
on two different – and basically contradictory –
assumptions. The first one (which is still true) states that no
victorious revolution has ever occurred in a purely imperialist
country up till now. The case of 1917 Russia is seen as an
exceptional case, a unique combination of under-development and
imperialism. But it is irrational, even childish, to recognize
as revolutions only those that have been successful. Once one
accepts that revolutionary processes did occur in 20th century
imperialist countries, surely the logical conclusion for a
revolutionist is to study them carefully so as to be able to map
out a course which will make defeat unlikely when they occur
again in the future.
The second assumption is that
whatever in the past triggered revolutions [23]
(revolutionary crises and processes) will never happen again.
Bourgeois society – the capitalist economy and parliamentary
democracy – are supposed to have achieved such a degree of
stability and “integrated” the mass of wage earners to such
an extent that they won’t be seriously challenged in any
foreseeable future. [24]
This assumption, which already prevailed during the postwar boom
(in obvious function of the undeniable increase in standard of
living and social security which was its by-product for the
Western proletariat) was seriously challenged in May 1968 and
its immediate aftermath, at least in Southern Europe (and
partially in Britain in the early seventies). It regained a
powerful credibility in the wake of the retreat of the
proletariat in the metropolitan countries towards essentially
defensive struggles after 1974-1975.
We should understand the nub of
the question. The seemingly a-prioristic assumption is in
reality a prediction which will be historically either verified
or falsified. It is in no way a final truth. It is nothing but a
working hypothesis. It assumes a given variant of the basic
trends of development of capitalism in the latter part of the
20th century: the variant of declining contradictions, of the
ability of the system to avoid explosive crises, not to say
catastrophes. In that sense, it is strikingly similar to the
working hypothesis of the classical version of reformism, i.e.
of rejection of a revolutionary perspective and revolutionary
strategy: that of Eduard Bernstein. In his book which launched
the famous “revisionism debate,” he clearly posited a
growing objective decline in acuity of inner contradictions of
the system as premises for his reformist conclusions: less and
less capitalist crises; less and less tendencies towards war;
less and less authoritarian governments; less and less violent
conflicts in the world. [25]
Rosa Luxemburg answered him succinctly that precisely the
opposite would be the case. And when under the influence of the
Russian revolution of 1905, Kautsky came the nearest to
revolutionary Marxism and was the undisputed mentor of Lenin,
Rosa Luxemburg and Trotsky [26],
he also explicitly identified the perspective of inevitable
catastrophes to which capitalism was leading as one of the main
pillars of Marxism’s revolutionary perspectives. [27]
When he moved away from revolutionary Marxism, he started to
consider these catastrophes as becoming more and more unlikely,
i.e. he started to share Bernstein’s euphoric working
hypothesis. [28]
What does the historical record
reveal? Two world wars; the economic crisis of 1929 and onwards;
fascism; Hiroshima; innumerable colonial wars; hunger and
disease in the third world; the ongoing ecological catastrophe;
the new long economic depression. They leave out that it has
been Rosa Luxemburg who has been proven more right than
Bernstein; and that it was the Kautsky of 1907 who has been
proven right by history and not the Kautsky of the 1914
“ultra-imperialism” theory. Today it seems truer than ever,
to paraphrase a famous formula of Jean Jaurès, that late
capitalism carries within itself a succession of grave crises
and catastrophes like clouds carry storms. [29]
One transforms that obvious
truth – obvious in the sense that is borne out by solid
historical evidence for three-quarters of a century – into a
meaningless caricature when one insinuates that revolutionary
Marxists except or predict permanent catastrophes, every year in
every in imperialist country, so to speak. Leaving aside the
lunatic fringe, serious Marxists have never taken that stand,
which doesn’t mean that they have never been guilty of false
analysis and erroneous evaluations regarding particular
countries. If one soberly analyses the ups and downs of
economic, social and political crisis in the West and Japan
since 1914, what emerges is a pattern of periodic upsurges of
mass struggles in some metropolitan countries which have at
times put revolutionary processes on the agenda. In our view,
the mechanisms leading in that direction remain operative today
as they were since the period of historical decline of the
capitalist mode of production was first posited by Marxists. The
burden of proving that this is no longer the case is upon those
who argue that today’s bourgeois society is somehow basically
different from that of 1936, not to say that of 1968. We
haven’t yet seen any persuasive argumentation of that nature.
The concept of periodically and
not permanently possible revolutionary explosions in imperialist
countries logically leads to a typology of possible revolutions
in the West, which sees these revolutions essentially as a
qualitative “transcroissance” of mass struggles and
mass experiences of non-revolutionary times. We have often
sketched this process of “overgrowing,” based not upon
speculation or wishful thinking but on the experience of
pre-revolutionary and revolutionary explosions which have really
occurred in the West. [30]
We can therefore limit ourselves to summarizing the process in
the following chain of events: mass strikes; political mass
strikes; a general strike; a general sit-down strike;
coordination and centralization of democratically elected strike
committees; transformation of the “passive” into an
“active” general strike, in which strike committees assume a
beginning of state functions, in the first place in the public
and the financial sector. (Public transport regulation, access
to telecommunications, access to saving and bank accounts
limited to strikers, free hospital services under that same
authority, “parallel” teaching in schools by teachers under
strikers’ authority, are examples of such inroads into the
realm of the exercise of quasi-state functioning growing out of
an “active” general strike.) This leads to the emergence of
a de facto generalized dual power situation with emerging
self-defence bodies of the masses.
Such a chain of events
generalizes trends already visible at high points of mass
struggles in the West: Northern Italy, 1920; July 1927 in
Austria; June 1936 in France; July 1948 in Italy; May 1968 in
France; the “hot autumn” of 1969 in Italy; and the high
points of the Portuguese revolution 1974-1975. Other general
strike experiences [31]
involving a similar chain of events were those of Germany 1920
and Spain (especially Catalonia) 1936-1937. (Albeit in a very
different social context, the tendency of the industrial
proletariat to operate in the same general sense in
revolutionary situations can also be seen in Hungary 1956,
Czechoslovakia, 1968-1969, and Poland 1980-1981.) Such a view of
proletarian revolutionary behavior in the imperialist countries
makes it easier to solve a problem which has haunted
revolutionary Marxists since the beginning of the 20th century:
the relation between the struggle for reforms (economic as well
as political-democratic ones) and the preparation for
revolution. The answer given to that problem by Rosa Luxemburg
already in the beginning of the debate remains as valid today as
it was at that time. [32]
The difference between the reformists and revolutionists does
not at all lie in the rejection of reforms by the latter and the
struggle for reforms by the former. On the contrary: serious
revolutionists will be the most resolute and efficient fighters
for all reforms which correspond to the needs and the
recognizable preoccupations of the masses. The real difference
between reformists and revolutionary Marxists can be thus
summarized:
- Without rejecting or
marginalizing legislative initiatives, revolutionary
socialists prioritize the struggle for reforms through
broad, direct extra-parliamentary mass actions.
- Without negating the need to
take into consideration real social-political relations of
forces, revolutionary socialists refuse to limited the
struggle for reforms to those which are acceptable to the
bourgeoisie or, worse, which don’t upset the basic social
and political relations of power. For that reason,
reformists tend to fight less and less for serious reforms
whenever the system is in crisis because, like the
capitalists, they understand the “destabilizing”
tendency of these struggles. For the revolutionists, the
priority is the struggle for the masses’ needs and
interests, and not the defence of the system’s needs or
logic, nor the conservation of any consensus with
capitalists.
- Reformists see the
limitation or elimination of capitalism’s ills as a
process of gradual progress. Revolutionists, on the
contrary, educate the masses in the inevitability of crises
which will interrupt the gradual accumulation of reforms,
and which will periodically lead to a threat of suppression
of conquests of the past, or to their actual suppression.
- Reformists will tend to
brake, oppose or even repress all forms of direct mass
actions which transcend or threaten bourgeois state
institutions. Revolutionists, on the contrary, will
systematically favor and try to develop self-activity and
self-organization of the masses, even in daily struggles for
immediate reforms, regardless of “destabilizing”
consequences, thereby creating a tradition, an experience of
broader and broader mass struggle, which facilitates the
emergence of a dual power situation when generalized mass
struggles – a general strike – actually occur. Thereby,
proletarian revolutions of the type sketched above can be
seen as an organic product – or climax – of broader and
broader mass struggles for reforms in pre-revolutionary or
even non-revolutionary times.
- Reformists will generally
limit themselves to propagating reform. Revolutionary
Marxists will combine a struggle for reforms with constant
and systematic anti-capitalist propaganda. They will educate
the masses in the system’s ills, and advocate its
revolutionary overthrow. The formulation and struggle for
transitional demands which, while corresponding to the
masses’ needs, cannot be realized within the framework of
the system, plays a key role here.
Doesn’t such a view of
“really feasible revolution” in the west seriously
underestimate the obstacle which the Western proletariat’s
obvious attachment to parliamentary democracy constitutes on the
road towards the overthrow of bourgeois institutions, without
which no victorious revolution is possible? We don’t think so.
In the first place, many
aspects of the legitimate attachment of the masses to democratic
rights and freedom is not at all an attachment to bourgeois
state institutions. It expresses, to use a clarifying formula of
Trotsky, the presence of nuclei of proletarian democracy inside
of the bourgeois state. [33]
The larger the masses’ self-activity, self-mobilization and
self-organization, the more the butterfly of democratic
workers’ power tends to appear out of its “bourgeois”
chrysalis. The fundamental issue will be one of growing
confrontation between the “naked core” of bourgeois state
power (the central government, the repressive apparatus, etc.)
and the masses’ attachment to democratic institutions which
they themselves control.
In the second place, there is
no reason to counterpose in an absolute and dogmatic way organs
of direct workers and popular power, and organs resulting from
undifferentiated universal franchise. Workers and popular
councils and their centralized coordination (local, regional,
national, international council congresses) can be more
efficient and democratic forms of making possible the direct
exercise of political, economic and social power by millions of
toilers. But if it is necessary to reject parliamentary
cretinism, it is likewise necessary to reject anti-parliamentary
cretinism. Whenever and wherever the masses clearly express
their wish to have parliamentary-type power organs elected by
universal franchise – the cases of Hungary, Poland and
Nicaragua are clear in that sense – revolutionists should
accept that verdict. These organs need not supercede the power
of soviets insofar as the masses have learned through their own
experiences that their councils can give them more democratic
rights and more real power than the broadest parliamentary
democracy alone; and insofar as the precise functional division
of labor between soviet-type and parliamentary-type organs is
elaborated into a constitution under conditions of workers
power.
Of course, soviet institutions
can and should also be elected on the basis of universal
franchise. The fundamental difference between parliamentary and
soviet democracy is not the mode of election but the mode of
functioning. Parliamentary democracy is essentially
representative, i.e. indirect democracy, and to a large extent
limited to the legislative field. Soviet democracy contains much
higher doses of direct democracy, including the instrument of
“binding mandates” of the electors for their representative
and the right to instant recall of these by their electors. In
addition, it implies a large-scale instant recall of these by
their electors. In addition, it implies a large-scale
unification of legislative and executive functions which,
combined with the principle of rotation, actually enables the
majority of the citizens to exercise state functions.
The multiplication of
functional assemblies with a division of competence serves the
same purpose. A key specificity of soviet democracy is also that
it is producers’ democracy, i.e. that it ties economic
decision-taking to work places and federated work places (at
local, regional and branch levels etc.), giving those who work
the right to decide on their workload and the allocation of
their products and services. Why should workers make sacrifices
in spending time, nerves and physical strength for increasing
output, when they generally feel that the results of these
additional efforts don’t benefit them, and they have no way of
deciding about the distribution of its fruits? Producers’
democracy appears more and more as the only way to overcome the
declining motivation (sense of responsibility) for production,
not to say the economy in its totality, which characterizes both
the capitalist market economy and the bureaucratic command
economy.
IV. The
Lessons of Third World Revolutions
The revolutionary processes in
the Third World since World War II have confirmed the validity
of the strategy of permanent revolution. Wherever these
processes have climaxed in a full break with the old ruling
classes and with international capital the historical tasks of
the national-democratic revolution (national unification,
independence from imperialism) have been realized. This was the
case of Yugoslavia, Indochina, China, Cuba, Nicaragua. Wherever
the revolutionary process did not culminate in such a full
break, key tasks of the national-democratic revolution remain
unfulfilled. This was the case of Indonesia, Bolivia, Egypt,
Algeria, Chile, Iran.
The theory (strategy) of
permanent revolution is counterposed to the traditional
Comintern/CP strategy since the middle nineteen twenties, to wit
that of the “revolution by stages,” in which a first phase
of “bloc of four classes” (the so-called “national”
bourgeoisie; the peasantry; the urban petty-bourgeoisie and the
proletariat) is supposed to eliminate by a common political
struggle the semi-feudal and oligarchic power structures,
including foreign imperialist ones. Only in a second phase is
the proletarian struggle for power supposed to come to the
forefront. This strategy first led to disaster in China in 1927.
It has led to grave defeats ever since. It is increasingly
challenged inside many CPs themselves.
It is of no avail to avoid
making this fundamental choice by the use of abstract formulas.
The formulas, “workers and farmers government” or, worse,
“people’s power” or “broad popular alliance under the
hegemony of the working class,” just evade the issue. What
revolutions are all about is state power. The class nature of
state power – and/or of the question which major fraction of a
given class exercises state power – is decisive. Either the
formulas just cited are synonymous with the overthrow of the
bourgeois-oligarchic state, its army and its repressive
apparatus, and with the establishment of a workers state; or the
formulas imply that the existing state apparatus is not to be
“immediately” destroyed – in which case the class nature
of the state remains bourgeois-oligarchic and the revolution
will be defeated.
When it is said that without
the conquest of power by the working class, without overthrow of
the state of the former ruling classes, the historical tasks of
the national-democratic revolution will not be fully realized,
this does not mean that none of these tasks can be initiated
under bourgeois or petty-bourgeois governments. After World War
II, most of the previously colonial countries did after all
achieve political national independence without overthrowing the
capitalist order. In some cases at least, India being the most
striking one, this was not purely formal but also implied a
degree of economic autonomy from imperialism which made at least
initial industrialization under national bourgeois ownership
possible. Starting with the late sixties, a series of
semi-colonial countries succeeded in launching a process of
semi-industrialization which went much farther (South Korea,
Taiwan, Brazil, Mexico, Singapore, Hong Kong are the most
important cases), often supported by substantial land reforms as
indispensable launching pads for these take-offs. The famous
controversy of the nineteen fifties and the nineteen sixties on
the so-called “dependencia” theory – the
impossibility of any serious degree of industrialization without
a total break with imperialism – has thus been settled by
history.
It is likewise incorrect to
interpret the theory of the permanent revolution as implying
that the overthrow of the old state order and the radical
agrarian revolution must perforce coincide with the complete
destruction of capitalist private property in industry. It is
true that the working class can hardly be supposed to tolerate
its own exploitation at factory level while it is busy, or has
already succeeded in, disarming the capitalists and eliminating
their political power. But from this flows only that the
victorious socialist revolution in underdeveloped countries will
start making “despotic inroads” into the realm of capitalist
private property, to quote a famous sentence of the Communist
Manifesto. The rhythm and the extent of these inroads
will depend on the political and social correlation of forces
and on the pressure of economic priorities. No general formula
is applicable here for all countries at all moments. The
question of the rhythm and the extent of expropriation of the
bourgeoisie is in turn tied to the question of the workers –
peasants alliance, a key question of political strategy in most
of the third world countries. Keeping capitalist property intact
to the extent of not fulfilling the poor peasants’ thirst for
land is obviously counter-productive. Hitting private property
to the extent of arousing fear among the middle peasants that
they too will lose their property is counter-productive from an
economic point of view (it could become also counter-productive
politically).
On balance, however, experience
confirms what the theory suggests. It is impossible to achieve
genuine independence from imperialism and genuinely to motivate
the working class for the task of socialist reconstruction of
the nation without the expropriation of big capital in industry,
banking, agriculture, trade and transportation, be it
international or national capital. The real difficulties only
arise when the borderline between that expropriation and the
tolerance of small and medium-sized capital (with all its
implications for economic growth, social equality and direct
producers’ motivation) has to be determined.
The historical record shows
that a peculiar form of dual power of confrontation between the
old and the new state order has appeared during all victorious
socialist revolutions in underdeveloped countries: dual power
reflecting a territorial division of the country into liberated
zones in which the new state is emerging, and the rest of the
country where the old state still reigns. This peculiar form of
dual power expresses in turn the peculiar form of the
revolutionary (and counter-revolutionary) processes themselves,
in which armed struggle (guerrilla warfare, people’s war)
occupied a central place. In the cases of China, Yugoslavia, and
Vietnam, this resulted from the fact that the revolution started
as a movement of national liberation against a foreign
imperialist aggressor/invader, while becoming increasingly
intertwined with civil war between the poor and the well-to-do,
i.e. with social revolution. In the cases of Cuba and Nicaragua,
the revolution started likewise as armed struggle against a
viciously repressive and universally hated and despised
dictatorship, again growing over into a social revolution.
One should of course not
simplify the pattern emerging from these experiences. At least
in Cuba and in Nicaragua (to some extent also in the beginnings
of the Indochinese revolution and in several stages of the
Yugoslav revolution) urban insurrections played an important
role. A successful general strike and a successful urban
insurrection decided the outcome of the Cuban and the Nicaraguan
revolutions. The proponents of the strategy of armed struggle
today generally adopt a more sophisticated and complex strategy
then in the sixties, combining guerrilla warfare, the creation
of liberated zones and the mobilization of mass organizations in
urban zones (including forms of armed self-defence) in order to
lead the revolution to victory. This combination seems
reasonable in many semi-colonial countries, where state
repression under pre-revolutionary conditions leaves no other
alternative to revolutionary strategy. We believe, however, that
this pattern should not be considered unavoidable once and for
all in all Third World countries, regardless of specific
circumstances and particular social-political relationships of
forces at given moments.
V. Political
Revolution in So-called Socialist Societies
The concept of political
(anti-bureaucratic) revolution in the bureaucratized societies
in transition between capitalism and socialism (bureaucratized
workers states) was first launched by Trotsky in 1933. It
resulted from the diagnosis of the growing contradictions of
Soviet society and from the prediction that these contradictions
could no longer be removed through reforms; and it was related,
therefore to the prediction that a self-reform of the
bureaucracy was impossible. [34]
Most left tendencies considered this concept, and the premises
on which it was based, as either a fantasy, or objectively a
call for counter-revolution. The overthrow of the bureaucratic
dictatorship could only lead to a restoration of capitalism:
that was the assumption.
These objections were
unfounded. Trotsky’s prognosis of political revolution, like
his analysis of the contradictions of Soviet society, appear as
one of his most brilliant contributions to Marxism. Since 1953,
we have witnessed a chain of revolutionary crises in Eastern
Europe: GDR June 1953; Hungary 1956; Czechoslovakia 1968; Poland
1980-1981. One can discuss whether similar crises didn’t also
occur in China, both in the nineteen sixties and the nineteen
seventies. (Mikhail Gorbachev himself calls his perestroika a
revolution and compares it with the political revolutions which
occurred in France in 1830, 1848 and 1870.) [35]
In all these concrete revolutionary processes, there was no
prevalent tendency to restore capitalism. This did not only
result from the objective fact that the overwhelming majority of
the combatants were workers who have no interest in restoring
capitalism. It was subjectively determined by the very demands
of these combatants, which in Hungary set up workers’ councils
with the Central Workers Council of Budapest leading the
struggle. Similar development occurred in Czechoslovakia and in
Poland. The line of march of the political revolution in the
USSR will be quite similar.
On the other hand, it cannot be
denied that attempts at self-reform of the bureaucracy have been
many – the most spectacular of them being the introduction of
workers’ self-management at factory level in Yugoslavia in
1950. While often instrumental in triggering off a “thaw” of
the bureaucracy’s stranglehold on society and enabling a
revival of mass activity and mass politization at various
degrees, these attempts have always failed to solve the basic
ills of these societies. This was especially true for the
historically most important of these attempts, the one initiated
by N.S. Khrushchev in the USSR. Indeed, today most of the
“liberal” and “left” Soviet historians and intellectuals
agree that the reason for the failure of Khrushchev was
insufficient activity from below. This, incidentally, is also
Gorbachev’s official version of the Khrushchev experience.
So the historical balance-sheet
is again clear: attempts at self-reform can start a movement of
change in the bureaucratized workers’ state. They can even
facilitate the beginning of a genuine mass movement. But they
cannot bring about a successful culmination of such change and
movement. For this, a genuine popular revolution is
indispensable. Self-reform of the enlightened wing of the
bureaucracy cannot be a substitute for such a revolution. The
bureaucracy is a hardened social layer, enjoying huge material
privileges which depend fundamentally on its monopoly on the
exercises of political power. But that same bureaucracy does not
play any indispensable or useful role in society. Its role is
essentially parasitic. Hence its rule is more and more wasteful.
It tends to become the source of a succession of specific
economic, social, political, ideological-more crises. Hence the
need to remove it from its ruling position is an objective
necessity for unblocking the march forward towards socialism.
For this, a revival of mass activity, in the first place
political activity of the working class, in needed. While a
revolution will have many implications in the field of the
economy, it will basically consolidate and strengthen the system
of collective ownership of the means of production and of
socialized planning, far from overthrowing it. That is why we
speak of a “political revolution” instead of a “social
revolution.” [36]
To a large extent, the
bureaucracy rules in function of the political passivity of the
working class; Trotsky even said through passive “tolerance”
by the working class. The historical-social origins of that
passivity are well-known: the defeats of the international
revolution; the pressure of scarcity of consumer goods and of
lack of culture born from the relative backwardness of Russia;
the consequences of the Stalinist terror; a disappointment of
historical dimensions, leading to a lack of historical
alternatives to the bureaucracy’s rule. But the very progress
of Soviet society during the last half century, achieved on the
basis of the remaining conquests of the October revolution and
in spite of the bureaucracy’s misrule, slowly undermines the
basis of that passivity. The stronger, more skilled and more
cultivated becomes the working class, the greater its
resentments and expectations clash with the slow-down of
economic growth and the manifold social crises which the
bureaucracy’s misrule and waste provoke. So conditions emerge
which tend to revive the working classes’ activity.
Timothy Garton Ash quotes a
remarkable memorandum by the new Polish Prime Minister,
Mieczyslaw F. Rakowski, which concludes with the prediction that
if the “socialist formation” does not find the strength to
reform itself, “the further history of our formation will be
marked by shocks and revolutionary explosions, initiated by an
increasingly enlightened people.” Indeed. But as Ash himself
clearly indicates, in spite of his favoring reforms moving
towards a restoration of capitalism tempered by a “liberal”
democracy, the difficulty lies precisely in the social
correlation of forces: the working class is not ready to pay the
price for a return to capitalism, i.e. massive unemployment and
inequality. So you can’t have generalized market economy plus
political democracy. You can only have partial market economy
plus political repression. So you can’t have radical reforms.
So the likelihood that you’ll have a political revolution is
growing. Ash himself rather cynically concludes: “It seems
reasonable to suggest that the reform has a rather higher chance
of minimal success – that is, of averting revolution – if
only because of the further diversification of social interests
which it will promote. The freeing of the private sector, in
particular, means that Hungary might yet have an entrepreneurial
bourgeoisie that will go to the barricades – against the
revolting workers. Capitalists and Communists, shoulder to
shoulder against the proletariat: a suitably Central European
outcome for socialism. To estimate the percentage chance of
peaceful transformation, by contrast requires only the fingers
of one hand. [37]
Yet, precisely because the
bureaucracy is not a new ruling class but a parasitic cancer on
the working class and society as a whole, its removal through a
political revolution by the workers does not require the type of
armed conflict which until now has accompanied revolutions in
class societies, including modern capitalist ones. It is more in
the nature of a surgical operation. This was confirmed in the
case of Hungary 1956 which went the farthest towards a
victorious political revolution. A significant part of the CP
apparatus and practically the whole army went over to the camp
of the workers (of the people). Only a tiny handful of secret
police agents opposed arms to the victorious masses in open
provocations, thereby provoking an overt conflict (and their own
sad fate) which otherwise could have been avoided. In
Czechoslovakia 1968 a similar trend was set in motion. In fact,
in all cases of such political revolutions witnesses up till
now, only foreign military intervention could prevent it from
becoming victorious nearly without bloodshed. One does not see
what force could replace such a foreign intervention in the case
of the USSR, probably not the Soviet army. And the capacity of
the KGB to repress 265 million people seems dubious to say the
least.
History has also confirmed the
utopian character of the idea that the construction of socialism
could be fully achieved in a single country or a small number of
countries. It has confirmed that the USSR (and the so-called
“socialist camp”) cannot escape the pressure of the world
market (or international capitalism): the pressure of wars and
of the permanent arms race: the pressure of constant
technological innovations; and the pressure of changing
consumption patterns for the mass of the producers. But far from
being an unavoidable result of that pressure, the bureaucratic
dictatorship undermines the revolution’s objective revolution
in the USSR and Eastern Europe would strengthen considerably
that resistance. It would make new advances towards socialism
possible. But we should not fall into the illusion that it could
even so, actually achieve a classless society of its own,
independently of revolutionary developments elsewhere.
VI. World
Revolution Today
The concept of the three
sectors of the world revolution refers to the different
strategic-historical tasks with which the revolutionary process
is confronted today. But this only represents the first step
towards a concretization of the concept of world revolution
today. The question of these sectors and their interaction, and
hence their growing unity, has also to be raised.
For decades, the apologists of
the Stalinist dictatorship used to say that revealing the dark
side of the Soviet (the Eastern European, the Chinese) reality
discourages the workers in the West from fighting to overthrow
capitalism. But history has fully confirmed that it is
impossible to conduct a fight for a good cause on the basis of
lies, half-truths or the hiding of truth. As it was impossible,
in the long run, to hide the revolting aspects of Soviet
reality, the mass of the workers in the West and Japan
(including those adhering to or voting for Communist Parties)
ended by assimilating them. What really discouraged and
demoralized them was not the revelation of these facts but the
facts themselves – including their decade-long suppression by
the Communist Parties and their fellow travellers. One of the
biggest subjective obstacles to a new development of
revolutionary consciousness among the Western working class is
the repulsive mask which Stalinism has put on socialism
(communism). By contributing to tearing off that mask, a
victorious political revolution in the East greatly advances the
cause of socialism the world over. It strengthens the struggle
against capitalism and imperialism instead of weakening it.
The idea that such a revolution
would at least weaken the USSR (or the “socialist camp”) at
state level and thereby change the military relationship of
forces in favor of imperialism is likewise unfounded. It is an
undeniable fact that the existence of the USSR in spite of the
bureaucratic dictatorship and theory of “peaceful
coexistence,” objectively contributed to the victory and
eventually the consolidation of the Chinese revolution and the
downfall of the colonial empires in the subsequent decades. But
parallel to that objective reality must be seen the fact that
the Soviet bureaucracy tried to obstruct the progress of the
Chinese revolution through the strategy it advocated, and played
a key role in the post World War II consolidation of capitalism
in Western Europe.
Furthermore, it is wrong to
disconnect military strength from its economic and social base
and from the political nature of governments. A Soviet Union,
not to say a “socialist camp,” governed through a
pluralistic socialist democracy and a broad consensus of the
majority of the toilers, would be much more efficient
economically, far more influential in the world, and thereby
much stronger militarily than the USSR of today. [38]
The concept of
interrelationship between the three sectors of the world
revolution is supported by the fact that while victorious
revolutions in the Third World countries can weaken imperialism,
they cannot overthrow it. In the epoch of nuclear weapons it is
obvious that imperialism can only be overthrown inside the
metropolis itself. But the main obstacle to that overthrow is
not the objective strength of imperialism or the bourgeois
state, nor the absence of periodically expressed demonstrations
inside the metropolis. The main obstacle is subjective: the
level of Western (and Japanese) working class consciousness and
the political quality of its leadership. Precisely for that
reason, new qualitative advances towards socialism in the USSR
and Eastern Europe, and the removal of the bureaucratic
dictatorships, would greatly assist in the solution of the
problem.
On the other hand, any leap
forward towards a victorious proletarian revolution in the West
and the most advanced semi-industrialized Third World countries
(like Brazil), which will occur under immeasurably more
favorable objective and subjective conditions than the Russian
October Revolution, will usher in material advantages which will
operate as a powerful stimulant for the toilers of all
countries, beginning with the Soviet toilers if they have not
yet overthrown the bureaucracy’s yoke at that moment. To
mention just one key aspect of an already victorious proletarian
revolution in an economically advanced country: the slogan of
the half-work day would play the same role as the slogan of
“Land, Bread, Peace” played in the Russian revolution. And
if that were realized no sector of the working class the world
over could stay impervious to the reality.
The potential relationship –
we say potential because it is obviously not yet a fact today
– between the three sectors of world revolution is premised on
historical/social unity of the world working class and the
strength of the forces operating towards the development of
conscious awareness of that unity. We know perfectly well how
strong the obstacles are on the road towards that political
consciousness. They have been enumerated and analyzed a thousand
times. What we want to stress is that they can be overcome by
the operation of still stronger objective trends. The unity of
the process of world revolution is related to the growing
internationalization of the productive forces and of capital –
exemplified in the emergence of the transnational corporation as
the typical late capitalist firm predominant in the world market
– which leads unavoidably to a growing internationalization of
the class struggle. Hard material reality will teach the
international working class that retreating toward purely
national defensive strategies (exemplified by protectionism)
leaves all the advantages to capital and increasingly paralyzes
even the defence of a given standard of living and of political
rights. The only efficient answer to an internationalization of
capital’s strength and maneuvers is international
coordination, solidarity and organization of the working class.
During the last decades, the objective need for world revolution
as a unity of the three world sectors of revolution has received
a new and frightening dimension through the growth of the
destructive potential of contemporary technological and economic
trends, resulting from the survival of capitalism beyond the
period of its historical legitimacy. The accumulation of huge
arsenals of nuclear and chemical weapons; the extension of
nuclear power; the destruction of tropical forests; the
pollution of air and water the world over; the destruction of
the ozone layer; the desertification of large tracts of Africa;
the growing famine in the Third World: all these trends threaten
disasters which put a question mark on the physical survival of
human-kind. None of these disasters can be stopped or prevented
at national or even continental level. They all call for
solutions on a worldwide scale. The consciousness about the
global nature of humanity's crisis and the need for global
solutions, largely overlapping nation-states, has been rapidly
growing.
Mikhail Gorbachev and his main
advisers and intellectual supporters tend to draw from a correct
perception of the globalization of problems and of the absolute
necessity to prevent a nuclear war the conclusion that
progressively, these global problems will be solved through an
increased collaboration between imperialist and “socialist”
states. They base themselves on two assumptions in that regard.
First they believe that a course towards world revolution
exacerbate inter-state relations to the point where the outbreak
of a world war would become more likely, if not unavoidable.
Second, they tactily presume that the inner contradictions of
capitalism will tend to decrease, that the real class struggle
will become less explosive, that trends towards increased class
collaboration will prevail in the 21st century. Both these
assumptions are utterly unrealistic. They are of the same type
as the hope to achieve the building of a really socialist
society in a single country, of which they represent in a
certain sense the logical continuation. The fact is that while
victorious or even unfolding revolutions have undoubtedly led to
counter-revolutionary interventions by imperialist powers, they
have on several occasions prevented larger wars from occurring.
Without the German revolution of 1918-1919, and the
revolutionary general strike in that country in 1920, the
preparations for a general strike in Britain that same year, a
major war of all imperialist powers against Soviet Russia would
probably have occurred. Without the victory of the October
revolution, the first World War would probably have been
prolonged at least for one if not for more years. The
revolutionary upsurge in Spain, France and Czechoslovakia in
1936 significantly slowed down the march toward World War II. If
it would have been victorious even only in Spain, not to say in
France and Czechoslovakia as well, World War II could have been
prevented. So to identify revolutions with unavoidable war is
just a misreading of the historical record. In fact, a
victorious revolution in France and Britain today, not to say in
the USA, would be the surest way to make world war impossible.
The real reasoning of the
neo-reformist Gorbachev version of “globalization” is based
on the classical reformist illusion of a decline in the
explosiveness and intensity of the inner contradictions of
capitalism and of bourgeois society. We have already dealt with
the unrealistic character of that assumption. It errs especially
by not taking into account the structural link between the
destructive uses of technology and economic resources on the one
hand, and competitive attitudes, competitive strife, private
property and market economy on the other hand. Bourgeois society
can never lead and will never lead towards a world without
weapons and without technological innovations applied regardless
of their costs to the natural and human ecology. You need
socialism to achieve these goals. And you have to achieve these
goals if humanity is to survive. The strongest justification for
world revolution today is that humankind is literally faced with
the long-term dilemma: either a World Socialist Federation or
Death.
Footnotes
1.
Precisely because the Marxist conception of revolution
encompasses the necessary dimension of mass action, the concept
of “revolution from above” is not strictly accurate,
although it was used by Engels and has, of course, a well
circumscribed significance. Joseph II’s reforms in Austria;
Tsar Alexander II’s abolition of serfdom; Bismarck’s
unification of Germany; the Meiji “revolution” in Japan,
were historical attempts to pre-empt revolutions from below
through radical reforms from above. To what extent they were
successful or failed in that historical purpose must be analyzed
in each specific case. The same applied mutatis mutandis
to Gorbachev’s reform course in the Soviet Union today.
2.
This was the epigram of the weekly Révolutions de Paris,
which started to appear from the end of August 1789 in Paris.
3.
See Barrington Moore Jr., The Social Bases of Obedience
and Revolt, M.E. Sharpe, White Plains, N.Y. 1978.
4.
This was the case during the days preceding the downfall of the
Shah in the streets of Teheran, a spectacle largely forgotten
because of the subsequent developments in that country.
5.
This does not automatically flow from the disintegration and
disarmament of the former army. The ruling class can make an
attempt to substitute a new bourgeois army to the old one, as it
did in Cuba after the downfall of Batista and in Nicaragua after
the fall of Somoza, but without success.
6.
This is the currently prevailing explanation of the reasons for
the Shah’s downfall: the combination of the “white
revolution” destabilizing traditional Iranian society and the
savagery of SAVAK.
7.
In Russia, the cause of the February-March 1917 revolution was
the rottenness of tsarism and the tremendous parasitical weight
of the peasants’ exploitation upon the overall economic
development of the country. The triggering factors of that
revolution were hunger riots of the Petrograd women workers
which the cossacks refused to repress. This expressed the
emergence of a de facto alliance between the working
class and the peasantry, contrary to what had occurred in the
repression of the 1905 revolution. There is, however, also a
deeper dialectical mediation between structure and conjuncture.
The specific social-political order in Tsarist Russia determined
both its participation in the first world war, and its
increasing incapacity to cope with the material and political
prerequisites of successful warfare. This incapacity in turn
deepened the social crisis in a dramatic way – leading to
chronic food shortages, to hunger riots and hence to the
decisive days of outbreak of the February-March 1917 revolution.
A similarly multi-layered analysis is needed to understand
contemporary revolutionary moments – including unsuccessful
ones, such as May 1968 in France. What went on in France during
the climax of the mass upsurge and the general strike deserves
to be seen as a revolution, although it was defeated. And the
triggering factor of the student revolt in Paris must itself be
seen in the context of a deeper structural crisis of social and
political relations. Useful here is the remarkable study by the
Soviet sociologist, Alex D. Khlopin, New Social
Movements in the West: Their causes and prospects of
developments, which complements Western Marxist
analyses.
8.
In Russia, the material interests of the cossacks as sons of
peasants, the connections of these interest to political
awareness on the one hand, and to the explosive crisis of the
relations of production in the countryside on the other hand,
all converge to explain the cossacks’ peculiar shift in
behavior, at a given moment, in a given place.
9.
It is, of course, possible that this breakdown is only temporary
and only lasts some weeks or months. But this doesn’t make the
collapse less real. In Germany – not only, but of course
especially in Berlin – this is what occurred in
November-December 1918. In France, this is what occurred at the
climax of May 1968. Indeed, it was recently confirmed that, at
that moment, General de Gaulle couldn’t phone General Massu,
the commander of the French army in Germany: he had lost control
of the whole telecommunication system in Paris as a result of an
effective general strike. An anonymous woman telephone operator
whom he finally succeeded in speaking to personally, refused to
obey his order. The decision of the strike committee prevailed.
These are the unknown heroines and heroes of revolution. This is
the stuff proletarian revolutions are made of.
10.
See Edward Luttwack, Technique of the Coup d’État
(1968); cf. interview with Stampa-Sera, August
8, 1988.
11.
Nevertheless Spinoza, who was himself skeptical about the
outcome of revolutions, explicitly proclaimed the people’s
right to revolution, more than a century before that same right
was ensconced in the Preamble of the American
Declaration of Independence first, in the French Declaration
of the Rights of Men and Citizens afterwards. To our
knowledge, the Yugoslav Constitution is today the only one which
not only contains explicitly that right, but even adds to it the
duty to make a revolution under specific conditions.
12.
The dogma of the basic “evil” of humankind is based in the
West on the superstition of Original Sin. Of late, it has
received a pseudo-scientific veneer with the Konrad Lorenz
school of the alleged universal agressivity of human beings,
which some psychologists then tend to generalize into a human
trend towards self-destruction. Better psychologists, in the
first place Sigmund Freud, pointed out that the human psyche
combines both a trend towards cooperation and a trend towards
self-destruction, Eros and Thanatos, to love
and to kill. If only the second one would have prevailed,
humankind would have disappeared a long time ago instead of
showing an impressive demographic-biological expansion.
13.
Two thousand years ago, the Jewish philosopher Hillel expressed
the contradictions of individual skepticism in a succinct way:
“If I am not for myself, who is for me? And if I am for myself
alone, what then am I? and if not now, then when?” Kant tried
to escape that dilemma through his categorical imperative, but
failed to apply it convincingly to social conflicts (see his
attitude towards the French revolution). Marx found the solution
in his categorical imperative to struggle against all social
conditions in which human beings are debased, oppressed, and
alienated.
14.
Revolutionary continuity was maintained by a handful of
followers of Babeuf who, through the person of Buonarotti,
helped to inspire Auguste Blanqui’s Société des Saisons,
which gave rise to anew revolutionary organization in the 1830s.
But for nearly forty years, there were very few organized
revolutionaries in the country which witnessed five revolutions
in the course of a century.
15.
The debate goes on, of course. René Sedillot (Le coût
de la révolution française, Paris, Perrin, 1987) is
the most brazen of the latter-day dragon-killers, who continue
the good fight against the French revolution after two
centuries. The sophisms on which he bases his argumentations are
revealed by the fact that he adds the victims of
counter-revolution, in the first place of Napoleon’s wars, to
the cost of the revolution. But he does not compare these
“costs” to those of the Ancien Régime’s dynastic
wars: the devastation of a quarter of Germany, the big famine in
France at the beginning of the 18th century, etc.
16.
The inclusion of Deng Xiaoping in this list is of course open to
serious challenge. Mao was not Lenin; he was rather a unique
combination of given traits of both Lenin and Stalin. Hence,
Deng Xiaoping, in spite of many right-wing tendencies in his
politics, cannot be considered the Thermidorian equivalent of
Stalin of the Chinese revolution.
17.
Incidentally, this is one of the objective bases for the second
“law of permanent revolution” formulated by Trotsky. For the
revolutionary process to continue after it starts to recede in a
given country, its center of gravity must shift to another one.
18.
Classical examples of defeated counter-revolutionary coups are
the Kornilov one in Russia, August 1917, the Kapp-von Luttwitz
putsch in Germany, 1920 and the Spanish military-fascist
uprising in July 1936 in Catalonia, Madrid, Valencia, Málaga,
the Basque country, etc.
19.
A democratic counter-revolution is a counter-revolution which
seeks to maintain essential features of bourgeois democracy,
including the legal mass labor movement, universal franchise and
a broadly free press, after having beaten back the workers’
attempts to conquer power and to arm themselves. Of course,
while engaged in suppressing the German revolution, Ebert, Noske
an Co. systematically curtailed democratic freedoms, forbade
political parties, suspended newspapers, requisitioned strikers
and even outlawed strikes, to preserve the bourgeois state.
Moreover, Ebert cynically lied before the All-German Congress of
Workers’ and Soldiers’ Councils (December 1918) when he
denied having brought soldiers to Berlin for repressive
purposes. He had actually done so, in direct connection with the
Imperial Army’s High Command, behind the back of his fellow
“people’s commissars” (ministers) of the Independent
Socialist Party. The repression started a few days later.
20.
This occurred in Germany throughout the country starting with
January 1919 in Berlin. It occurred in Barcelona after the May
days in 1937, in Greece starting with December 1944, in
Indonesia in 1965, just to quote some examples. Courageous left
socialists like the prewar Austrian social-democrats and
Salvador Allende in Chile did not refuse to fight
counter-revolution arms in hand, but they refused to organize
and prepare the masses systematically for this unavoidable
showdown and deliberately left the initiative to the enemy,
which meant courting disaster.
21.
Revolutionists cannot “cause revolutions,” nor can they
“provoke” them artificially (this is the basic difference
between a revolution and a putsch). Engels even went further and
stated: “Die Leute die sich ruhmen, eine Revolution
gemacht zu haben, haben immer noch am Tage darauf gesehen, dass
sie nicht wussten, was sie taten, dass die ‘gemachte’
Revolution, jener die sie hatten machen wollen, durchaus nicht
ähnlich sah” (letter to Vera Sassulitch of April 23,
1885, MEW, Band 36, p.307). [“The people who
boast of having made a revolution have always seen only the next
day that they hadn’t know what they were doing, that the
revolution they had ‘made’ didn’t look like the one they
had wanted to make.” – Translation by MIA]
22.
The concept of “combined revolution” is also applicable to
some imperialist countries, but with a different ponderation of
the combined elements from that of third world countries. E.g.
the combination of proletarian revolution and self-determination
of oppressed national minorities in Spain; the combination of
proletarian revolution and Black and Hispanic liberation in the
USA.
23.
E.g. in Finland 1917-1918; in Austria 1918-1919, 1927, 1934; in
Germany 1918-1923; in Italy 1919-1920, 1944-1945, 1969; in Spain
1931-1937; in France 1936, 1968; in Portugal 1974-1975.
24.
Some argue that the impossibility of escaping “technology
compulsion” (technologischer Sachzwang) constitutes
today an unsurpassable obstacle on the road to proletarian
revolution and “Marxian socialism.” This is an unproven
assumption, based upon the petitio principii that
technology somehow develops and is applied independently from
the social interests of those who have the means (under large
scale commodity production: the capital) to apply it.
25.
See Eduard Bernstein: Die Voraussetzungen des
Sozialismus und die Aufgaben der Sozialdemokratie
(1899). [published in English under the title Evolutionary
Socialism. – Note by MIA]
26.
On Kautsky’s evolutions away from revolutionary Marxism in
1909-1910, its turning point (his capitulation to the Parteivorstand
on the censorship that body applied to his booklet The
Road to Power) and its political outcome in his
opposition to Rosa Luxemburg’s campaign in favor of political
mass strikes, see Massimo Salvadori, Karl Kautsky and
the Socialist Revolution, NLB, London 1979, pp.123 ff.
27.
Karl Kautsky, Les Trois Sources du Marxisme
(1907), ed. française, Spartacus, Paris 1969, pp.12-13.
28.
Kautsky’s articles on ultra-imperialism in which he considered
inter-imperialist wars more and more unlikely, started to appear
from 1912 on. The final one had the unfortunate fate of
appearing in Die Neue Zeit on the aftermath of
the actual outbreak of World War I.
29.
We have developed this idea further in our article The
reasons for founding the Fourth International and why they
remain valid today. International Marxist Review,
Summer-Autumn 1988.
30.
Ernest Mandel, Revolutionary Marxism To-day,
New Left Books, London 1979.
31.
The case of the German workers’ answer to the Kapp-Luttwitz
coup of 1920 and of the Spanish workers’ answer to the
fascist-military uprising of July 1936 – in a more limited way
also the Italian workers’ uprising of 1948 – helps to
integrate into this typology the question of the proletariat’s
capacity to answer massively counter-revolutionary initiatives
of the bourgeoisie. This will remain on the agenda in the West
in the future as it was in the past. But this does not justify
any refusal to recognize that the process of proletarian
revolutions likely to occur in the West and in Japan will most
probably be quite different from these particular examples, as
well as from the revolutionary processes which we witnessed in
Yugoslavia, China, Indochina, Cuba, Nicaragua during and after
World War II.
32.
See Norma Geras, The Legacy of Rosa Luxemburg
(New Left Books, London, 1976) on this, and on Rosa being one of
the founders, together with Trotsky, of a theory of dual power
emerging from workers’ mass strikes.
33.
Trotsky, Was Nun? Schicksalsfragen des deutschen
Proletariats, January 1932.
34.
Leon Trotsky first formulated that conclusion in 1933 in his
article The Class Nature of the Soviet State (October
1, 1933), Writings of Leon Trotsky 1933-1934,
p.101f.
35.
On the question of how far that characterization is legitimate,
see Ernest Mandel, Beyond Perestroika, Verso,
London 1988.
36.
On the theoretical foundations of the definition of “political
revolution” and the analysis which leads to it, see Ernest
Mandel, Bureaucratie et production marchande, Quatrième
Internationale, No.24, April 1987.
37.
The New York Review of Books, October 27, 1988.
38.
The Mexican sociologist Pablo Gonzales Casanova has tried to
refute the legitimacy of the political revolution in the
bureaucratized workers states on the basis of a hierarchy of
revolutionary tasks on a world scale. As long as imperialism
survives, revolutionists (socialists, anti-imperialists)
everywhere in the world should give priority to the fight
against that monster over and above all other struggles. (See
his La Penetración metafísica en el Marxismo europeo,
in isabado, supplemento de Unomasuno,
8/1/1983). Underlying that reasoning is the hypothesis that an
ongoing, not to say a victorious, political revolution in a
bureaucratized workers’ state somehow weakens the fight
against imperialism. But that supposition is completely
unfounded, for the reason we have advanced.
|