The first impression of the
USSR is that of hypertrophy, of the omnipotence of the state.
Given that, the first question for a Marxist is the following:
which are the material foundations of the state and what is its
place in human society?
Marx and Engels clearly
established the general relationship between penury, the social
division of labour, the alienation of certain social functions
to the profit of a separate group of people – the bureaucracy
– and the origins, as much as the continual experience, of the
state:
‘It is clear that so long
as human labour was still so little productive that it
provided but a small surplus over and above the necessary
means of subsistence, any increase of the productive forces,
extension of trade, development of the state and of law, or
foundation of art and science, was possible only by means of a
greater division of labour. And the necessary basis for this
was the great division of labour between the masses
discharging simple manual labour and the few privileged
persons directing labour, conducting trade and public affairs,
and, at a later stage, occupying themselves with art and
science.’ [1]
‘The second distinguishing
characteristic is the institution of a public force which is
no longer immediately identical with the people's own
organization of themselves as an armed power. This special
public force is needed because a self-acting armed
organization of the people has become impossible since their
cleavage into classes ... This public force exists in every
state; it consists not merely of armed men, but also of
material appendages, prisons and coercive institutions of all
kinds, of which gentile society knew nothing.’ [2]
I. The
social division of labour, state and poverty
The withering away of the state
and social classes – the same thing in the eyes of Marx and
Engels – presupposes a level of development in the universal
productive forces which makes possible the ending of poverty and
the integral development of every individual. The submission of
these developed individuals to the tyranny of social and labour
division is no longer inevitable. Or, to paraphrase Engels, the
‘affairs of society’ can now be regulated by all and not by
a special apparatus.
‘Only the immense increase
of the productive forces attained by modern industry has made
it possible to distribute labour among all members of society
without exception, and thereby to limit the labour-time of
each individual member to such an extent that all have enough
free time left to take part in the general – both
theoretical and practical – affairs of society.’ [3]
And Engels makes it explicitly
clear that the ‘affairs of society’ includes all the
functions of the state in class society. The withering away of
the state is thus the return of the exercise of these functions
to society itself, without the existence of special apparatuses,
that’s to say without bureaucracy.
In The German Ideology,
Marx and Engels had already stated that the precondition of
communism was ‘a great increase of productive forces’, to
the universal (worldwide) level: ‘because without it want is
merely made general, and with destitution the struggle for
necessities and all the old filthy business would necessarily be
reproduced.’ [4] It
follows from this fundamental thesis of historical materialism
that the absence of socialism, in as much as it is the first,
inferior stage of communism in the Soviet Union and in other
similar societies, has three material causes, namely: 1. the
insufficient level of the development of productive forces; 2.
the isolation of these societies from the industrial, hegemonic
nations and 3. the resurrection of the struggle for the
satisfaction of material needs which necessarily results in a
return to the ‘old filthy business ...’. Trotsky expressed
this in the clearest fashion in The Revolution Betrayed:
‘If the state does not die
away, but grows more and more despotic, if the
plenipotentiaries of the working class become bureaucratised,
and the bureaucracy rises above the new society, this is not
for some secondary reasons like the psychological relics of
the past, etc., but is a result of the iron necessity to give
birth to and support a privileged minority so long as it is
impossible to guarantee genuine equality (...) The basis of
bureaucratic rule is the poverty of society in objects of
consumption, with the resulting struggle of each against all.
When there is enough goods in a store, the purchasers can come
whenever they want to. When there is little goods, the
purchasers are compelled to stand in line. When the lines are
very long, it is necessary to appoint a policeman to keep
order. Such is the starting point of the power of the Soviet
bureaucracy. It “knows” who is to get something and who
has to wait ...’ [5]
The state as controller,
executive of the ‘affairs of society’ (the accumulation by
one group of the social surplus; territorial administration;
military affairs; the norms of cohabitation between men and
women; the creation and maintenance of infrastructure, etc)
distinct from immediate economic activities (production and
distribution) embodies itself in a series of apparatuses which,
as Engels reminds us in Anti-Duhring, rends
itself autonomous from society, transforms itself from
society’s servant to its master. When the spokespersons for
Solidarnosc referred to such a situation in Poland, they were
Marxists without knowing or wanting to be so – and much better
Marxists than the leaders of the PUWP (Polish United Workers
Party – Trans.) who denied this manifest reality.
In the Soviet Union and in
other similar social formations, it is evident that the state
has not started to wither away. It continues, on the contrary,
to extend itself as a powerful independent force erected above
society. The leaders of the CPSU frankly preach its continual
reinforcement (cf. the new programme of the CPSU, 1986). This
proves that we are still a long way from a classless, socialist
society, that strong social tensions exist and that the
regulation of these social contradictions demands the existence
of the overdeveloped apparatus of bureaucracy:
‘The state is therefore by
no means a power imposed on society from without (...) Rather,
it is a product of society at a particular stage of
development; it is the admission that this society has
involved itself in insoluble self-contradiction and is cleft
into irreconcilable antagonisms which it is powerless to
exorcise.’ [6]
Revolutionary marxists do not
accuse the Stalinist faction and its successors in the
‘communist parties’ in power of having ‘caused’ the
monstrous growth of the state and the bureaucracy by
‘betrayal’ or by ‘political errors’. The opposite is
true. Revolutionary marxists explain the victory, the political
line and the ideology of the Stalinist faction and its
successors by material conditions and higher social factors. The
Stalinist faction and its successors can be reproached (in the
measure where ‘reproaches’ play a political role in
scientific socialism) with the following:
- That they hide social
reality in justifying the bureaucracy with a specified
ideology, a ‘false consciousness’ and, as a result,
abandon marxism and historical materialism in the
interpretation of society. From that they trick the working
class of their own country, and throughout the world, by
spilling out their lies.
- That in the name of
‘communism’ and of ‘marxism’ they have unleashed a
process of exploitation and repression against workers,
youth, the peasantry, women and national minorities on a
massive scale, which constitutes crimes against socialism
and the proletariat.
- That by their political
practice they have not limited poverty and bureaucratic
excess to the barest minimum, but that they have developed
them without measure. This means they have not acted, and do
not act, in the interests of socialism and the proletariat
as a class, but that they have subordinated their interests
to the specific interests of the privileged bureaucracy.
The general question posed by
this marxist explanation of the overdeveloped state and of the
bureaucracy in the Soviet Union is the following: weren’t the
Mensheviks right in opposing the October revolution, against
Trotsky and Lenin, with the argument that Russia was not mature
enough for socialism? The historic response to that question is
that the process of the world socialist revolution has
to be conceptually separated from that of the finished
construction of a socialist society without class. In fact
Russia was certainly not ‘mature’ enough for the
establishment of such a society. Up until 1924 this was the
common point of view of all revolutionary marxists: not only of
Lenin, Trotsky, Rosa Luxembourg, Bukharin, Zinoviev, Lukacs,
Gramsci, Thalheimer, Korsch, Radek etc, but also of Stalin. But the
world was mature enough for socialism. In fact, in Anti-Dühring
Engels already considers this to be a established fact.
What was already true in 1875
was incomparably more so in 1917. Now, the appropriation of the
means of production by the workers’ state is a political act,
which isn’t linked only to existing material conditions but
also to existing subjective conditions. On the basis of the
discovery of the law of combined and unequal development Trotsky
was able to predict from 1905-1906 that, in the framework of
the imperialist world, and given its unique combination of
socio-economic backwardness and political maturity, the
proletariat of certain less developed countries, like Russia,
would have the chance to break the power of the capitalist state
before such an eventuality might be seen in more developed
industrial nations. Imperialism simultaneously hampers the full
development of the objective conditions for socialism in the
backward countries (the complete development of capitalism) and
the subjective conditions for socialism in the highly developed
industrial countries (the full development of working class
consciousness). But it is in precisely a combination of these
two processes that a concrete form of the world socialist
revolution emerges, which may start in countries such as Russia,
but which will not end up in the full development of a socialist
society except by its extension to the most advanced industrial
nations. Rosa Luxemburg expressed it succinctly: ‘In Russia
the problem can only be posed: it cannot be resolved in Russia.
And it is in this sense that the future belongs everywhere to
“bolshevism”’. [7] It
is in these predictions, confirmed by history, that the complete
tragedy of the 20th century is contained.
The October revolution, was not
a means for the ‘development of socialism in one country’
but was a motor for the world socialist revolution: such was,
from the beginning, the historic justification that Lenin,
Trotsky, Luxemburg and their comrades gave it. Let’s listen
once again to Rosa (one could also add dozens of citations from
Lenin, Trotsky, Bukharin, Zinoviev):
‘Let the German Government
Socialists cry that the rule of the Bolsheviks in Russia is a
distorted expression of the dictatorship of the proletariat.
If it was or is such, that is only because it is a product of
the behaviour of the German proletariat, in itself a distorted
expression of the socialist class struggle. All of us are
subject to the laws of history, and it is only internationally
that the socialist order of society can be realized. The
Bolsheviks have shown that they are capable of everything that
a genuine revolutionary party can contribute within the limits
of historical possibilities. They are not supposed to perform
miracles. For a model and faultless proletarian revolution in
an isolated land, exhausted by world war, strangled by
imperialism, betrayed by the international proletariat, would
be a miracle. What is in order is to distinguish the essential
from the non-essential, the kernel from the accidental
excrescencies in the politics of the Bolsheviks. In the
present period, when we face decisive final struggles in all
the world, the most important problem of socialism was and is
the burning question of our time. It is not a matter of this
or that secondary question of tactics, but of the capacity for
action of the proletariat, the strength to act, the will to
power of socialism as such. In this, Lenin and Trotsky and
their friends were the first, those who went ahead as
an example to the proletariat of the world; they are still the
only ones up to now who can cry with Hutten: “I
have dared!”.’ [8]
With the first world war, a
series of virtually uninterrupted revolutions broke out, caused
by the internal contradictions of imperialism and the capitalist
mode of production, intensified by the war. These revolutions
were highly stimulated by the October revolution and by the
foundation of the soviet state, but they were not caused by
them. The real process of the world socialist
revolution, with the possibility of victory in the advanced
industrial countries like Germany and Italy, was encouraged by
the soviet state. During that period the possibility of the
realisation of socialism on a world scale progressed, despite
the impossibility of realising socialism in Russia. The October
revolution was thus completely justified from an historic point
of view.
II. Penury
and commodity production
The contradiction between
commodity production and a society of associated producers,
that’s to say a socialist society as an inferior phase of
communism, is one of the base elements of historical
materialism. For Marx and Engels, the battlefield of commodity
production was not at all limited to the capitalist mode of
production. ‘Political economy begins with commodities,
with the moment when products are exchanged, either by
individuals or by primitive communities.’ [9]
Now, in the first volume of Capital, Marx
describes how products do not become merchandise unless they
result from private works executed independently of each
other. From the moment that work loses its private
character, when it becomes immediately social, when its
organisation between various diverse sectors of activity does
not result from the spontaneous decisions of individuals, units
of production or companies, but from decisions taken a
priori by the whole of society, mercantile production
disappears:
‘Within the co-operative
society based on common ownership of the means of production,
the producers do not exchange their products; just as little
does the labour employed on the products appear here as the value
of these products (...) since now, in contrast to capitalist
society, individual labour no longer exists in an indirect
fashion but directly as a component part of total labour
(...).What we have to deal with here is a communist society,
not as it has developed on its own foundations, but,
on the contrary, just as it emerges from capitalist
society; which is thus in every respect, economically,
morally, and intellectually, still stamped with the birthmarks
of the old society from whose womb it emerges. Accordingly,
the individual producer receives back from society – after
the deductions have been made – exactly what he gives to
it.’ [10]
Given the persistence and
hypertrophy of the apparatus of the bureaucratic state, the
persistence of merchant production is thus a conclusive proof
that, from the point of view of historical materialism, in the
Soviet Union and in other similar social formations, socialist
society or socialist economy do not exist, no more than
fully developed socialisation of the means of production or
process of production. Apologists for the soviet bureaucracy
(supported by the benevolent smiles of western bourgeois and
petit-bourgeois ideologues) contest this in two ways. On the one
hand they say that Marx and Engels were mistaken on the ‘real
movement’ of socialism and, on the other, that practice has
proven that socialism can co-exist with a ‘strong state’ and
with commodity production. They remind us that, in this context,
the two masters repeated continually that communism isn’t a
goal to reach but a real movement which abolishes ‘the
existing state of things’, meaning private property. This
reductive point of view is based on the manifest falsification
of a citation in The German Ideology:
‘... with the abolition of
the basis of private property, with the communistic regulation
of production (and, implicit in this, the destruction of the
alien relation between men and what they themselves produce),
the power of the relation of supply and demand is dissolved
into nothing, and men get exchange, production, the mode
of their mutual relation, under their own control again.
Communism is for us not a state of affairs which is
to be established, an ideal to which reality [will]
have to adjust itself. We call communism the real
movement which abolishes the present state of things. The
conditions of this movement result from the premises now in
existence.’ [11]
Marx and Engels say that the
abolition of ‘the existing state of things’ oughtn’t to be
limited to the abolition of private ownership of the means of
production. It has to include at least the following:
- The abolition of commodity
production and the withering away of money (‘the power of
the link between supply and demand is reduced to
nothing’).
- The abolition of the
exchange of consumer goods, at least inside the commune.
- The control of the producers
over the product of their work and over their conditions of
work, which includes, amongst other things, the power of the
associated producers to dispose of the means of production
for consumer goods.
- The control of the people
themselves over ‘their mode of reciprocal behaviour’,
which excludes the existence of a repressive apparatus
separate from society.
There is no need to enumerate
the extensive empirical data in order to prove that the Soviet
Union and other similar formations are far from having fulfilled
these conditions. There has not yet been a real movement
anywhere in the world which has abolished ‘the existing state
of things’. There is no socialist society. Yet the
bureaucracy’s apologists accuse revolutionary marxists, and
other ‘critics from the left’ of consciously ‘elevating’
the demands of socialism in such a manner as to be able to
demonstrate that in the Soviet Union and elsewhere, reality
doesn’t attain the ‘ideal’. [12]
According to them, that would be ‘historical idealism’, a
‘normative utopia’, a ‘moralism’ substituting itself for
the categories of historical materialism.
To which we respond that
historical materialism implies explicitly that the scientific
categories (here including ‘norms’) are the product of
real social relations and not the product of ‘false
reasoning’ or of a diabolical ‘anti-communism’. The material
base of the ‘categories’ of merchandise, value and
money, in the Soviet Union and other similar societies, is the
absence of sufficient socialisation of production. Work does not
yet have an immediately social character. There is not yet
direct access of the producers to the means of production and to
consumer goods. In the same fashion, the producers are not yet
associated producers. Thus there is not total abolition of
private work or private property.
In other words: it isn’t
because social conditions in the USSR do not conform to the
‘norms’ of Marx that they are ‘non-socialist’ and
‘bad’. Such reasoning would, in effect, be idealistic and
‘normative’. It is because abundant empirical proof shows
that its functions are ‘bad’, that’s to say still
partially exploitative, very oppressive and alienating, that
they are ‘non-socialist’. The fact that they no longer
conform to Marx’s definition of socialism confirms that
Marx’s norms were correct about what socialism must be. These
norms necessary for socialism reveal themselves to be neither
‘idealist’ nor utopian concepts, but the conditions
necessary for the coming into being of a non-exploitative and
non-oppressive society without class. Neither in the Soviet
Union or elsewhere does one encounter a ‘really existing
socialism’. The bureaucracy, the international bourgeoisie and
their respective ideologues affirm the opposite because such an
affirmation corresponds to their interests. The interests of the
one is to hide or excuse the inequality, the material privileges
and the monopoly of power which exists in the Soviet Union. The
interests of the other is to discredit socialism in the eyes of
western workers, in presenting the real situation in the Soviet
Union and elsewhere as ‘really existing socialism’.
Less well informed apologists
add the following: ‘left opportunist’ critics of Soviet
society confuse socialism with communism. That which is demanded
of a socialist society is only possible in a communist society.
These apologists forget the clear characterisation of Lenin:
‘It is this communist
society, which has just emerged into the light of day out of
the womb of capitalism and which is in every respect stamped
with the birthmarks of the old society, that Marx terms the
“first”, or lower, phase of communist society... The means
of production are no longer the private property of
individuals. The means of production belong to the whole of
society. Every member of society, performing a certain part of
the socially-necessary work, receives a certificate from
society to the effect that he has done a certain amount of
work ...’ [13]
They forget that this
definition of socialism is found equally in the above mentioned
citations of Marx and Engels, that the whole Marxist tradition
from 1875 to 1928, with the possible exception of Karl Kautsky,
bases itself on the same definition. Stalin himself repeated it
up to June 1928! [14] A
simple question of definition? Certainly not. One cannot
maintain that commodity production and the law of value continue
to operate in a socialist society except in rejecting the whole
of volume one of Marx’s Capital, his analysis
of merchandise, of value, of the value of exchange and the law
of value. This implies not only the rejection of Marx’s
definition of socialism, but also the rejection of his whole
analysis of capitalism and the origins of class and the state,
that’s to say the complete rejection of historical
materialism. Everyone has the right to think that history has
refuted the theories of Marx. But no one has the right to call
themselves ‘marxist’, that is to pretend to adhere to the
scientific discoveries of Marx, and at the same time to advance
theories on the essence and dynamic of commodity production, of
value and the law of value, of money, of capitalism and
socialism, which are in complete disagreement with those of
Marx.
The remark of Marx according to
which ‘bourgeois law’ still exists under socialism (the
first, inferior phase of communism) cannot in any manner imply
the existence of commodity production and of the law of value.
The above mentioned citation from Marx’s Critique of
the Gotha Programme explicitly affirms the opposite. Despite
the disappearance of commodity production and of the law of
value under socialism, bourgeois law continues to dominate,
because there is only formal equality (exchange of
equivalent quantities of individual work, immediately recognised
as social work). From the fact that different individuals have
different needs and different capacity to produce quantities of
work, some will largely be able to satisfy their needs and
others will not. What exists today in the Soviet Union, isn’t
formal equality in the distribution of consumer goods, to which
Marx refers with the formula ‘bourgeois law’, but an
enormous and growing formal inequality. In exchange for
seven hours of work, an unskilled manual worker receives x
in consumer goods; a high bureaucrat receives for the same seven
hours of work 10x or 20x in consumer goods (in
not only taking into consideration salary in money but also the
distribution and nature of the goods and services).
This ‘bourgeois law’ goes
well beyond Marx’s notion concerning the first, socialist
phase of communism. And from this it follows, as it follows from
the persistent existence of commodity production and the law of
value, that the ‘struggle for existence’, the general
struggle for personal enrichment, the cold calculation of
‘personal advantage’, egoism, careerism and continual
corruption dominate society (even if it is to a lesser degree
than under capitalism). Such a social dynamic does not result,
in the first place, from ‘residual capitalist ideology’ or
from ‘western influence’, but principally from the
existing socio-economic structure of the Soviet Union itself.
We find yet again the same
poverty, the same insufficient development of productive forces
which has already served to explain the rising up and
over-development of the state and the bureaucracy. Distribution,
juridical relations and the conditions of power are not able to
raise themselves to a qualitatively superior level than that
which is allowed by the level of development of the productive
forces. The fashion in which distribution is organised, and thus
by whom and how it is arranged, depends in the final analysis on
how much can be distributed, that is how much has been produced.
The strongest will, the most praiseworthy intentions, the
highest idealism, cannot change this in the long term. For as
long as Soviet society is unable to combine with the most
advanced industrial sectors of the world (western Europe, north
America, Japan), there will be no socialism there. A socialist
outcome continues to depend on the outcome of international
capitalism, on the victory or defeat of the world proletariat,
thus on the future of the world revolution.
This frees us from another
misunderstanding concerning the attitude of marxist
revolutionaries with regard to the USSR. The fact that marxists
underline that the market relations which persist in the Soviet
Union and elsewhere prove a socialist society doesn’t yet
exist does not imply that they ‘demand’ that the party of
the working class finishes ‘immediately’ with commodity
production and with money, that they should ‘immediately’
abolish the state, and other similar absurdities. Commodity
production and value cannot be ‘abolished’ arbitrarily, just
as the state cannot be artificially ‘suppressed’. They can
only wither away progressively. The fact that in the
Soviet Union, rather than withering away they continue to grow
is an indispensable part of the scientific, objective marxist
analysis of these societies, an irrefutable proof of the
non-existence of socialism. But this is not a basis for
irresponsible and irrational suggestions. In the given internal
and external conditions, the survival of commodity production
and circulation of money, and even that of the workers’ state,
is inevitable. If they were ‘abolished’ a daily unravelling
and disintegration of the existing relations of production would
result not in favour of socialism but, in the final
accounting, in favour of the restoration of capitalism.
Concrete suggestions made for
the reform of the economy of soviet society (1922-1933), then
the programme for political revolution elaborated by
revolutionary marxists have never called for an immediate
‘halt’ to commodity production. Rather, they have called for
its optimal inclusion in a system of socialised production and
planning which targeted simultaneously an optimal development of
the productive forces in the long term and real
socialist relations of production. The one cannot be
arbitrarily separated from the other.
No increase in the existing
productive forces, no socialism. But without the emergence of
true socialist relations of production, the construction of
socialism is just as impossible. It is not a question of
producing ‘in the first place’ so many tons of steel, cement
or a quantity of cars, houses, etc., until the producers
suddenly become (by what miracle?) the masters and mistresses of
their working conditions and of their lives. Simultaneously,
and by a constant process of interaction, progress has to be
made on the production and work productivity front on the one
hand, and of the release of worker self-organisation in the
economy and in the state (the effective power of soviets,
democratic socialism) on the other hand. Without decisive
progress on worker self-organisation, social equality and
political democracy, the sources of further development of the
productive forces will gradually dry up, one after the other.
From this point of view it is completely misplaced to accuse
marxist revolutionary critics, as Lukacs has, of the Stalinist
thesis of ‘socialism in one country’, or as a replacement
solution:
‘... socialism resulting
from revolutionary war or the return to the circumstances
before the 7th of November, that’s to say the dilemma
between adventurism and capitulation. Because of this dilemma
history does not justify a rehabilitation of Trotsky. In that
which concerned the decisive strategic questions of the epoch,
Stalin was completely right.’ [15]
This falsification accepts the
legends of the thermidorian bureaucracy, which are directly
refuted by all the documents concerning the discussions at the
heart of the CPSU and of the Comintern from 1923 to 1933. Far
from having been the prisoners of the dilemma described by
Lukacs, Trotsky and the left opposition maintained – initially
against Stalin/Zinoviev, later against Stalin/Bukharin, and
finally against the remaining Stalinist faction, the CPSU having
become monolithic – that communists had to simultaneously
accomplish two tasks. They had to accelerate the
industrialisation of the Soviet Union, introduce economic
planning, raise the technical base of agriculture (with the help
of industrialisation) and to re-organise it on a cooperative
basis, but only with the freely given consent of the
peasantry. At the same time, they had to expand the
revolution on an international level according to the laws
and internal demands of the struggle of the classes in each
country (and not according to the conjunctural necessity of
the defence the Soviet Union). This line equally rejected
capitulation and adventurism, as is indicated in Trotsky’s
critique of the programme of the Comintern:
‘During the Third Congress,
we declared tens of times to the impatient Leftists:
‘Don’t be in too great a hurry to save us. In that way you
will only destroy yourselves and, therefore, also bring about
our destruction; Follow systematically the path of the
struggle for the masses in order thus to reach the struggle
for power. We need your victory but not your readiness to
fight under unfavourable conditions. We will manage to
maintain ourselves in the Soviet republic with the help of the
NEP and we will go forward. You will still have time to come
to our aid at the right moment if you will have gathered your
forces and will have utilized the favourable situation.’ [16]
Finally, in the framework of
the theory of permanent revolution, the understanding of the law
of combined and unequal development does not at all imply that
people in less industrialised countries can do nothing for their
own liberation and must await the victory of the proletariat in
the advanced industrialised nations in order to create the basis
for the successful construction of socialism. On the contrary,
Trotsky had arrived at the conclusion that only a socialist
revolution in the backward countries was able to liberate them
from the barbarous heritage of the past which weighted on them.
In the age of imperialism, capitalism is incapable of cleaning
the stables as it has done for the most part in the west. That
reason is sufficient in itself to fully justify socialist
revolutions in the third world. Revolution alone is able to
resolve the unaccomplished tasks of the development of
socialism. But the process cannot be completed on the restricted
economic and social bases of single countries. It has to be
spread to the leading industrialised countries when the
conjunction of class struggle permits.
III. The
hybrid combination of market economy and bureaucratic despotism
Is it the result of our
analysis that, given the insufficient development of productive
forces in the Soviet Union, the bureaucracy has become a leading
class: or even a ‘state capitalist’ class, or perhaps a
‘new class’? Certainly not. To refute this mechanistic
thesis implies a closer examination of a contradictory
overlapping between commodity production and the operation of
the law of value on the one hand and bureaucratic domination on
the other. This contradictory relationship (which leads to
specific, hybrid relations of production which, historically,
are not capable of automatic reproduction) must be inserted in
the more general problematic of societies in transition between
historically ‘progressive’ modes of production, to cite the
celebrated formula of Marx.
We have already noted that the
restriction of the functioning of commodity production only to
capitalism contradicts the theory of historical materialism
developed by Marx and Engels. Through exchange value and
commodity production, the effect of the law of value existed
centuries before the emergence of the capitalist mode of
production. What distinguishes the different forms of capitalist
small commodity production is the fact that only under
capitalism do commodity production and value become generalised.
It is only at the heart of this mode of production that the
means of production and labour power become general commodities.
Even though both capital and capitalism, and their
contradictions, might already be present in small commodity
production, they are still just embryos. In order to develop
fully a whole series of economic and social conditions have to
be created to permit the embryo to grow and mature. In the west,
and in the great civilisations of the east, this process has
taken 2,500 years. In the lesser developed countries it is still
incomplete today.
The obstacles on the road of
this process are enormous. To only mention one: the necessity of
separating the producers – the great majority of them being
peasants – from all direct access to the land. Without this
condition the complete development of the capitalist mode of
production and the transformation of the direct producers into
wage earners are impossible. But the separation of the peasantry
from their means of production, and thus elementary subsistence,
demands an enormous transformation of property relations in
the country. [17]
Slave plantations and the landed properties of the state, as
much as the original village communities with actual power of
access to the land for the peasants (be it in the ‘asiatic
mode of production’ or in that of ‘pure’ feudalism) are
enormous obstacles for such a transformation. They have to be
annihilated. Additional economic, social and political
transformations in production and commerce, in the town as in
the country, are also necessary. The slowness of their
maturation leads during long periods of small commodity
production, even in the advanced regions of western Europe, to
coexistence between preponderantly non-capitalist relations of
production and progressively emerging capitalist relations of
production.
This phase of transition from
feudalism to capitalism produced a hybrid combination of
commodity production and the production of use values alone. The
law of value functioned in the sphere of commodity production
under a form proper to such a transitional society. But for a
long period it hardly functioned, or functioned not at all, at
the level of the village. A European peasant in the late middle
ages, an Indian or Chinese peasant of the eighteenth century, a
Mexican or African peasant of the nineteenth century, does not
change the volume or nature of his production according to
fluctuations in market price, so long as this production is
intended primarily for his own subsistence. Land taxes and rent,
war or famine can augment or diminish (sometimes drastically)
the total part of use value products which remain to him for his
own consumption. But this fact does not transform him into a
commodity producer, dependent on the market, that’s to say on
the law of value. For that to happen there must be a
transformation of the property relations in the village
(property relations understood not only in an juridical but also
economic sense). The actual separation of the peasant
from free access to the land is necessary. We would define the
logic of such a hybrid society by the formula: the law of value functions
in such a society but does not dominate it. The
distribution of available socially productive resources between
different branches isn’t determined by the law of value, but
rather by custom and tradition, the needs of the peasants, their
techniques of production, their habits, their community
organisation, etc. The analysis that Marx made of this state of
things is well known.
Such hybrid production
relations do not necessarily lead to stagnation of productive
forces and of society. A contradiction between the traditional
economy and commodity production develops slowly, by means
including the expansion of usury and commercial and
manufacturing capital. In the long term it is able to produce an
economic and social dynamic which eventually leads to the
predominance of the law of value and of the capitalist mode of
production. Nevertheless this involves a concrete historical
process which must be concretely studied and of which the
reality must be empirically demonstrated. It cannot be deduced
by such abstract syllogisms as: the emergence of commodity
production – automatic predominance of the law of value –
capitalism – domination by the capitalist class.
The analogy with the economic
and social structure of the Soviet Union is striking. The same
as in pre-capitalist societies, commodity production persists in
a society in transition between capitalism and socialism. But in
both cases it concerns non-generalised, partial,
commodity production. Consumer goods and the means of production
exchanged between agricultural cooperatives and state
enterprises are as much commodities as those products involved
in external trade. But the great mass of the means of production
are not commodities. The greatest part of labour is not either. [18]
For the majority of machines, natural resources or labour, there
is not, properly speaking, a market.
The distribution of social
resources between different branches of production is not
effectuated on the basis of the law of value. Machines and work
forces are not displaced from branches that might have a lower
‘rate of profit’ to branches that might have a superior rate
of profit. Prices and profits (in any case purely for accounting
purposes, and coming from arbitrary prices) are not the signals
which determine or re-orientate investment. It is not the law of
value but the state, that’s to say the bureaucracy, which
decides in the last instance the proportions of social product
which will be invested and that which will be consumed, as much
as the dynamism of the economy taken in its entirety. The Soviet
economy is not a generalised market economy. It is an economy
of the central allocation of resources, a centrally planned
economy.
It is not so much a ‘pure’
economy of allocation. It is a hybrid combination of an economy
of allocation and of commodity production in which the law of
value doesn’t dominate but continues to function. The
influence of the law of value, in the final analysis, limits
bureaucratic despotism and restricts it within unbreakable
frontiers. This is what Sweezy and Magdoff do not admit,
though they reject – correctly – the existence of the
pretended ‘economic laws of socialism’, but wrongly deduce
the possibility of a more or less unlimited economic despotism
of the bureaucracy.
In part bureaucratic
arbitrariness is circumscribed by objective internal
constraints, that is by the limits of material resources that
the economy can allocate. In effect the bureaucracy is able to
determine, in a despotic fashion, that certain industrial
branches should have priority in receiving rare resources, such
as technically advanced resources. It is also able to
successively accord priority to heavy industry, to the armaments
industry, to the space programme, gas pipelines to Europe, etc.
But it cannot liberate itself from the laws of enlarged
reproduction. [19] Each
disproportionate allocation of resources to the benefit of one
distinct branch of the economy leads to disproportions in the
whole which undermines the productivity of labour, including in
the heavy and armaments industries, and which directs, for
example, a part of soviet economic resources towards the
importation of food products in place of machines or modern
technology, etc. In any case this is only part of the problem. A
thousand links unite non-market sectors in commodity-money
relationships, in spite of all the terror, of all the repression
and of all the despotism of the bureaucracy.
Also, in part, the
arbitrariness of the bureaucracy is restrained by the world
capitalist market. On the world market it is the law of value
which dominates. There the only definitive thing is
price, determined by the law of value. All the external commerce
of the soviet bloc (including trade internal to COMECON) is
definitively based on the prices of the world market.
The hybrid nature of the
transitional society of the USSR is clearly reflected in the dual
structure of prices. One series of prices are determined by
the law of value. Another series of prices are fixed arbitrarily
by the planning authorities. The second group of ‘prices’
still dominates in the Soviet Union. That is why the soviet
economy is still a centrally allocated economy – protected by
the state monopoly on external trade – in other words, a
planned economy. But the greater the weight of external commerce
at the heart of the gross national product of a soviet bloc
country, the greater the constraints of the world market, and
the more ‘planned’ prices are subject to the law of value.
This influences the distribution of resources even in the heart
of the state sectors of the economy. It is from this fact that
the socio-material possibilities of a planned economy, that is
the centralised allocation of decisive economic resources, find
themselves restrained. The conflict between the ‘political’
wing and the ‘technocratic’ wing of the bureaucracy, between
‘central’ planning and the managers of enterprises, are, in
the last analysis, reflections of these objective
contradictions.
Even though the persistent
existence of commodity production and the despotic domination of
the bureaucracy flow from the same source (the isolation of the
socialist revolution in a relatively industrially backward part
of the world) this despotism remains linked to the collective
ownership of the means of production, to the planned economy and
to the state monopoly on external trade: commodity production
and the functioning of the law of value cannot, in the long
term, generalise themselves without breaking the despotism of
the bureaucracy.
It is here that we find the
decisive reason why the bureaucracy has not become a dominant
class. It cannot become so by evolving into a ‘new’
dominating class but only by transforming itself into a
‘classic’ capitalist class. In order for a ‘new’
non-capitalist ‘bureaucratic’ mode of production to emerge
the soviet bureaucracy will have to definitively liberate itself
from the influence of the law of value. This would demand not
only the dissolution of the relations of distribution based on
exchange in the interior of the Soviet Union but also the total
emancipation of the USSR in relation to the world market, in
other words the elimination of capitalism on a world scale, at
least in the most important industrial nations [20],
which depends, in its turn, on the final outcome of the struggle
between capital and labour on a world scale. For as long as that
struggle is not definitively concluded, that’s to say as long
as we do not see either the victory of the world socialist
revolution, or the self-destruction of the bourgeoisie and the
working class in a new barbarism or in the radioactive dust, the
future of the Soviet Union remains undecided.
A new dominant class
presupposes a new mode of production, with its own internal
logic, with its own laws of motion. Up until now, nobody has
been able to identify the laws of motion of this ‘new mode of
bureaucratic production’ – for the simple reason that they
don’t exist. On the other hand it has been possible for us to
determine the specific laws of motion of a society in transition
from capitalism to socialism, frozen in an intermediate phase by
the bureaucracy. The empirical data from the last thirty years
has amply confirmed the operation of these laws of motion. [21]
Partisans for the notion of the
‘bureaucratic class’ froth in cursing the bureaucracy. But
at the same time they are compelled to admit that these
‘assassins, criminals, thieves, tyrants’ play a
partially progressive role. This is not accidental: in
history each dominating class has, in effect, played a
progressive role at the dawn of its domination. For
revolutionary marxists, the incontestable partially
progressive aspects of the interior and exterior role of
the soviet state flows precisely from the fact that it still a
workers’ state, even if a bureaucratised workers’ state. The
working class was, and remains today, the only socially
progressive force on the world scale, the only force capable of
resolving the crisis of humanity, the crisis of the 20th
century. As for the non-proletarian aspects of the
bureaucratised workers’ state, all that concerning the
particular interests and the specific nature of the bureaucracy
in its role as a social layer (its antagonism towards the
working class, its appropriation of a part of social surplus,
its conservative role in the international arena), they are
profoundly and totally reactionary. [22]
In history ruling classes have
been able to maintain their domination in the long term on the
single basis of property (in the economic sense of the term: the
ability to dispose of social surplus and the means of
production). The fate of state functionaries in the Asiatic mode
of production is very significant in this regard.
In China, during the initial
phases of each dynasty, the objective function of the
bureaucracy was to protect the state and the peasantry from the
ambitions of the landed nobility (the gentry) in order to permit
enlarged reproduction (irrigation works, centralisation of
surplus, guarantee of adequate productivity of labour in the
villages, etc), and this allowed the payment – often very
generous – of the bureaucracy by the state, from the
centralised surplus. But the bureaucrat remained dependant on
the arbitrariness of the state (of the court, of the
emperor). His position was never sure. [23]
He wasn’t able to guarantee that his son or his nephew would
obtain the same good position as a bureaucrat. That’s why
during the second half of each dynastic cycle a general and
progressive integration of the landed nobility (gentry) and the
bureaucracy is effected. The bureaucrats become the owners of
private property, initially of money and valuable furnishings,
and then of land (this was frequently by a formally
‘illegal’ process, comparable to the appropriation of raw
materials and finished products by the ‘black market’ in the
Soviet Union). In the same measure that state bureaucrats
established themselves in the landed nobility, the
centralisation of social surplus was undermined, the power of
the state was weakened, the pressure on the peasantry was
reinforced and the peasant’s income was reduced. Agricultural
labour productivity diminished. Rural exodus, peasants’
revolts, banditry and insurrections become more general. Finally
the dynasty collapses. A new dynasty – often originally from
the peasantry – emerges and restores the relative independence
of the state and its bureaucracy in relation to the landed
nobility.
An analogous process has
developed in the last decades in the heart of soviet society. As
long as the absolute poverty in consumer goods persisted there
– that is mostly from 1929 to 1950 – the necessity of
satisfying their immediate needs pushed the bureaucrats to force
the workers into doubling and tripling their efforts. When these
immediate needs were assured, the soviet economy was confronted
with the same problem that has characterised all pre-capitalist
societies. Dominant classes or layers (castes, etc.), whose
overall privileges are reduced to the benefit of private
consumption, have no long term objective interest in a durable
increase in production. [24]
That is why increases in production and consumption of luxuries
goes hand in hand with waste, senseless luxury, individual
decadence, (alcoholism, orgies, drugs). In this sense the
conduct of the nobility of the Roman empire, of the nobility of
the French court of the 18th century, of the Ottoman nobility of
the 19th century, of the tsarist nobility on the eve of the
Russian revolution is almost identical.
The parallel of the factions of
the upper layers of the soviet bureaucracy and the parasitical rentiers
of monopoly capitalism is evident. It is only the
entrepreneurial capitalist class that is forced by the
pressure of competition (that is of private property and
generalised commodity production) to conduct itself in a
fundamentally different manner. If competition weakens,
capitalism tends to stagnation – so said Marx. But competition
flows from private property (once again in the economic sense of
the term). Without the one, the other loses all significance.
In the course of the 1950’s
the critics of our thesis, according to which the USSR remains a
transitional society, yelled their heads off that what prevailed
in that country was ‘production for production’s sake’,
which leads to a permanent, exceptionally high level of growth.
Our analysis permitted us to predict that the opposite was going
to happen, given the peculiar nature of the bureaucracy. History
has already judged.
From this an empirically
verifiable dynamic of the soviet economy is possible. The slower
the growth of the soviet economy, the more one part of the
bureaucracy pushes for a decentralisation of the means of
production and the social surplus, in the name of the increase
in the ‘rights of the directors’, in effect an illegal
appropriation of productive resources for private
production and profit. This progressively saps centralised
planning. This leads to the reinforced operation of the law of
value and gives a definitive opening to a tendency to the
restoration of capitalism. In parallel with this process, there
is a growing division at the heart of the soviet bureaucracy,
and above all the growing opposition of the working class. [25]
Because the workers note in practice that private appropriation
and private property cannot impose themselves other than to
the detriment of full employment and at the price of an ever
greater inequality. Examples from Poland and the Soviet
Union confirm that the working class fights tenaciously for full
employment and against social inequality. [26]
This is why worker self-management, combined with an imaginary
‘socialist market economy’, only masks the problem in place
of resolving it. There is no real power of decision for
the worker collectives (and thus no real self-management) if the
law of value is able to impose business closures on them. There
is no real ‘market economy’ if worker collectives can
effectively prevent fluctuations in employment.
In brief, if one witnesses in
the Soviet Union and similar societies an embryonic
transformation of parts of the bureaucracy into a ‘ruling
class’, it is not a ‘new bureaucratic ruling class’ that
is involved, but indeed the embryo of the good old class of
capitalists and private proprietors of the means of
production. If this transformation of bureaucrats into
capitalists is realised it would reflect the process by which
the law of value would finally reach dominance, rather than just
influence, in the soviet economy. Such a process demands a
generalisation of commodity production, that’s to say a
transformation of the means of production and of labour
power into commodities. To reach this point the process
would have to destroy the collective ownership of the means of
production, institutionally guaranteed full employment, the
dominance of centralised planning and the state monopoly on
external trade. This cannot only happen on the economic terrain
and would demand a new historic defeat of the soviet working
class on the social and economic level. This defeat hasn’t
happened yet. [27]
Forces that favour an
anti-bureaucratic political revolution (and which, in the long
term, are stronger than those which would lead to a
restoration of private property and capitalism) push soviet
society in an opposite direction: that of a contraction in the
operation of the law of value, of the reinforcement of the
collective ownership of the means of production, of the resolute
limitation of the field of activity of the bureaucracy and of
social inequality, of the withering of the state. They operate
objectively in favour of a new, decisive progress towards
socialism and the world revolution.
The October revolution and the
bureaucratic domination that resulted from its isolation cannot
be explained except by a combination of specific limits
of Russian ‘internal development’ (a ‘barbaric’
capitalism in a semi-feudal state under strong external
imperialist influence; a feeble ‘indigenous’ bourgeoisie; a
relatively stronger working class, more concentrated and more
conscious) and of the prodigious development of world capitalism
and of the world proletariat in the imperialist epoch. For the
self same reason the Russian bureaucracy is unable to transform
itself into a ‘ruling class’ for as long as the fate of
capitalism isn’t decided internationally one way or another.
And for the same reason the ‘old filthy business’ which
re-emerged in the USSR after the victory of the revolution
wasn’t able to take the form of a new class society but that
of a bureaucratisation of society in transition between
capitalism and socialism.
IV. The
concrete impact of the bureaucracy on social reality
Our revolutionary marxist
interpretation of the Soviet Union isn’t based on an
‘objectivist’, still less an ‘economist’ conception of
history. [28] We do not
affirm in any case that the ‘subjective factor’ (the
political line applied by the leadership of the state and the
party) and its relationship with the average ‘national’ and
‘international’ class consciousness of the proletariat
should have had, or has, a purely marginal impact. The objective
circumstances (the degree of the development of the productive
forces) certainly impose strict limits on the politics of the
state and the party. Even the best revolutionaries in the Soviet
Union would not be able today (not to speak of 1920, of 1927, of
1933 or of 1953) to completely abolish commodity production, the
monetary economy, the state and the bureaucracy.
But, within these objective
limits, the range of political possibility is more extended than
one would generally believe. It is nearly twenty five years
since we tried to explain (in chapter 16 of our Traité
d’Économie Marxiste) the theoretical basis of these
possible political variants. Nobody, up until now, has given a
theoretical reply nor have they refuted the arguments.
In every society where there
exists a more or less continuous enlargement of the forces of
reproduction of social product it will subdivide itself, not
into two, but into three base sectors:
- the funds consumed in
production (A), which allows the reconstitution of the
labour force and the means of production exhausted in the
course of production;
- the funds of accumulation
(B), constituted by the sum of the means of production and
of the supplementary consumption of the producers,
rendered expendable by the enlarged reproduction, measured
in use values (in this context we evidently do not
consider the relations of the value of exchange, because we
are not only discussing the capitalist mode of production);
- the funds for non-productive
consumption (C) (also including armaments production) which
contributes nothing to the enlargement of future
reproductive forces, again in terms of use values. [29]
The bureaucratic economic
ideology (supported by innumerable western ideologues, including
pseudo and semi-marxists) insists on the fact that a limitation
of spending on production for consumption is necessary to
guarantee a high level of accumulation for economic growth which
will then assure in the long term ‘optimal growth’
of consumption. This is what would explain the elevated rate of
accumulation of the soviet economy (an average of 25% of
national revenue per annum). This thesis is practically and
theoretically incorrect for two fundamental reasons: firstly, it
neglects the fact that direct funds for consumption for the
producers really represents the funds of indirect means of
production. Each distancing from what the producers
consider to be necessary for their consumption causes a
relative, or even absolute, fall in labour productivity.
Supplementary investments made possible by this relative or
absolute fall in the consumption of the producers ends up with
the rates of growth of final production. The 25% rate
of accumulation initially implies an annual growth of 7%, then
of 5%, then of 4%, then only 3%. Western economists refer to
this as a ‘capital growth coefficient’ in the USSR: the
official soviet economists define the same phenomenon with the
concept of ‘slowing of the [duration of] the rotation of fixed
funds’ [30] –
secondly this ideology neglects the fact that the producers who
consume less than they would like to, who consume goods of poor
quality, and who are not satisfied with their working and living
conditions (including with the absence of political and civil
rights) work in an indifferent fashion, if not
consciously slowly. Thus they must be forced to work.
In a capitalist economy this is
essentially regulated by the labour market, that’s to say by
fluctuations in wages, by the fear of losing one’s job, by
periodic mass unemployment during economic crises and
depressions, etc. In the Soviet Union these constraints only
functioned marginally, or not at all: it is not at all
simply a capitalist society. In place of the laws of the
market there is administrative control and pressure and
repression are in operation: the despotism of the bureaucracy. These
circumstances explain precisely the over-development of
controllers and police of all sorts: the hypertrophy of the
bureaucracy and of the state. This ends up with an enormous
growth in the above mentioned C (the resources for
non-productive consumption). From this fact B diminishes more
than in the case of a reasonable increase in A. The expansion of
unproductive expenses reduces or suppresses the benefits of
growth which are believed to be obtainable by limiting the
consumption of the producers (A).
Herein lies the complete
secret of the politics and the economic history of the
bureaucracy, of its initial successes and of its more and more
apparent setbacks. Because of the internal contradictions
in its management and its planning, the bureaucracy is more and
more the brake on the expansion of the productive forces. This
obstacle on the road to socialism must be eliminated before
advances can be made again.
In the Soviet Union the size of
the bureaucracy, as much as that of commodity production, is
much larger than that which is objectively inevitable. The
interaction between objective inevitability and bureaucratic
politics (that’s to say the product of specific
bureaucratic interests) determines soviet reality and
its dynamic. The consequences of this interaction can be
summarised in the formula: an enormous waste. A recent
chief of the bureaucracy, Yuri Andropov, estimated that one
third of annual working hours were wasted. One would not be
able to find a more overwhelming judgement on the management of
the soviet economy by the bureaucracy.
From the time of Marx, marxist
revolutionaries have always been aware of the danger of the
working class, come to power, would be oppressed by its own
bureaucrats. In The Civil War in France, Marx sketched out the
measures by which the State-Commune – the dictatorship of the
proletariat – would have to distinguish itself from the
bourgeois state: election of all officials by universal
suffrage; recall by the electors; limitation of payment to the
average worker’s wage. Marx adds:
‘The Commune made that
catchword of bourgeois revolutions – cheap government – a
reality by destroying the two greatest sources of expenditure:
the standing army and state functionarism.’ [31]
In the introduction that he
wrote for this pamphlet of Marx, Engels explicitly affirmed:
‘From the outset the
Commune was compelled to recognize that the working class,
once come to power, could not manage with the old state
machine; that in order not to lose again its only just
conquered supremacy, this working class must, on the one hand,
do away with all the old repressive machinery previously used
against it itself, and, on the other, safeguard itself
against its own deputies and officials, by declaring them all,
without exception, subject to recall at any moment.’
(our emphasis). [32]
Starting from this base Lenin
was able to draw the following conclusion:
‘The whole point is that
this “sort of parliament” will not merely “establish the
working regulations and supervise the management” of the
“apparatus”, but this apparatus will not be
“bureaucratic”. The workers, after winning political
power, will smash the old bureaucratic apparatus, shatter it
to its very foundations, and raze it to the ground; they will
replace it by a new one, consisting of the very same workers
and other employees, against whose transformation into
bureaucrats the measures will at once be taken which were
specified in detail by Marx and Engels.’ (our emphasis) [33]
Toward the end of his conscious
life, Lenin recognised with bitterness that these guarantees
were not working in the Soviet Union. For this reason he
qualified the existing state as a workers’ state with
bureaucratic deformations, a bureaucratically deformed
workers’ state. [34]
This formula isn’t the invention of Trotsky or of the fourth
international. It comes from Lenin, who employed it notably in
justifying strikes in the USSR. (Between times, the right to
strike has been expunged from the constitution of the Soviet
Union and from that of the People’s Republic of China). It is
no longer permitted to talk of the ‘withering away of the
bureaucracy’. The soviet bureaucracy is forced to recognise
that in its social formation, and in similar social formations,
powerful social contradictions exist. [35]
After the XX Congress of the CPSU, the failure of the Chinese
cultural revolution, and the explosion of Solidarnosc in Poland,
it would be difficult to deny it. But it cannot allow that one
takes account of its contradictions by social concepts.
It has to limit itself to ‘explanations’ historically or
even purely moralistically ideological: ‘errors’,
‘deviations’, ‘bad conduct’, ‘factionalism’,
‘cliquism’, ‘crimes’, absence of ‘communist
morality’ (one no longer says proletarian morality), etc.
It is true that, at times, a
critical soviet author may risk himself by going further. But he
must, from the start, entangle himself in contradictions because
he cannot go right to the conclusion of his thoughts. He also
risks violent reprimands from the authorities. It is this that
the soviet philosopher Butenko predicted in another situation.
It happened to him after he had denounced, in the light of
events in Poland, ‘the deformations’ of the Polish system
from 1948-1949, that’s to say right from the very start, also
to say they have lasted for more than 30 years! So, he wrote
that a deformation of socialism could consist of ‘the common
ownership of the means of production ... were able to be
replaced ... by the property of the bureaucratic state, separate
from the workers’. What’s more, ‘the mechanisms of power
in the interests of the workers and by the workers themselves
could be replaced by a mechanism of workers’ power but not in
their interests’. Is this only true in the People’s Republic
of Poland and not for the USSR? We don’t need to reply: te
fabula narratur (roughly ‘are you joking’ – Trans)?
And what to think of the following conclusion:
‘The analysis of these
contradictions is a task heavy with responsibility[indeed,
indeed, E.M.] which touches on the interest of
diverse groups [which groups? Why this kind, indulgent,
appeasing way of talking? E.M.] and for which each
imprecise remark [Only the imprecise? Perhaps even more so for
each precise remark? E.M.] may be used to the
detriment of society [Why are the interests of a ‘group’
suddenly identified with the interests of society, although
they are mutually contradictory? E.M.] as much as to
the disadvantage of the researcher in question [Here’s the
real problem! Who is able to utilise it? The proletariat as
the ruling class? Or the plenipotentiaries of the party, of
the state and of the bureaucracy?].’
Butenko went as far as to
advance the conclusion:
‘These manifestations of
deformation of socialism produce themselves each time on a
concrete historical base, which are normally parasitic
eruptions on the real process of socialist growth, and which
are undertaken by determined groups in their own interests.’
(our emphasis) [36]
Who are these mysterious
‘determined groups’? Why aren’t they named? Are they not,
precisely, the bureaucracy?
The same thing goes for the
most liberal of non-soviet apologists. And so Georges Lukacs
starts his commentary on the XX Congress of the CPSU in squarely
rejecting the ‘cult of personality’ as an explanation for
stalinism. He makes the first timid steps towards a social,
materialist explanation of the phenomenon.
‘My first, almost immediate
reaction to the XX Congress was directed beyond the person,
against the organisation: against the bureaucratic machine
which has produced the cult of personality and which, it
follows, is dedicated to its permanent and expansive
reproduction.’ [37]
But the deviation towards an
historic idealism is immediately at work. Instead of placing the
autonomy of the machine in the context of a social conflict
of interests, using the traditional methods of historical
materialism, Lukacs explains the enormous crimes of Stalin –
the tyrant who killed more communists than Hitler; the bill runs
to some 15 million soviet people – by the false ideas of
Stalin:
‘I have not completely
mastered this material. But already these passing and
fragmentary commentaries are able to show you that with Stalin
it was not in any way a question of isolated, occasional
errors, as many have wanted to believe for a long time.
It was rather about a false system of perception,
which gradually developed.’ [38]
In other words: the bureaucracy
was not working to enthrone the ‘cult of personality’ and
‘Stalin’s false system of ideas’ in the service of
material interests which confronted the working class as a
foreign social force. The stubborn defence of its monopoly of
power is not explained by the fact that this power constitutes
the base of its material privileges. No, the ‘false’ ideas
of Stalin (which emerged in the special situation in the USSR in
the thirties) have produced the total and arbitrary authority of
the bureaucracy. Isn’t this a complete rupture with historical
materialism? That which is able to explain this rupture for a
marxist as educated and intelligent as George Lukacs is his
willingness to find excuses for the bureaucratic dictatorship,
rather than to explain it scientifically (and also, in passing,
to justify his own capitulation before this dictatorship for
decades).
Hanging from Lukacs idealistic
theses is the ‘objectivist-historicist’ interpretation in
the style of Elleinstein who explains the Stalin phenomenon by
‘historic circumstances’ in ignoring once again the specific
social phenomenon of the bureaucracy.
To sum up: isolated in a less
developed country, the Russian socialist revolution was not able
to deploy itself in the direction of the dictatorship of the
proletariat and of the construction of a socialist society
without class, in the way that classical marxist theory had
foreseen. Insufficient production created generalised poverty.
In these conditions, and given the modest cultural level of the
proletariat, it gradually lost the direct exercise of political
power to the benefit of a machine of functionaries: the
bureaucracy.
The international and Russian
proletariat was yet too weak (mostly subjective reasons
regarding the former, objective reasons for the latter) to
guarantee the progressive limitation of the market and monetary
economy and the victorious international extension of the
revolution in the more advanced countries. But the growing
crisis of imperialism and capitalism, together with the real
force of the proletariat and the partial extension of the
revolution prevents the restoration of capitalism in the USSR.
From this follows the specific manner of play of the law of
value and the new division of labour, based on poverty, in
soviet society: not under the form of the emergence of a
dominant new class, but on the over-development of a
bureaucratic layer (caste) not yet liberated from collective
ownership of the means of production and of the centralised,
planned economy.
This bureaucratic layer enjoys
growing material privileges and a monopoly on political power to
guarantee them. But it is at the same time obliged to limit its
privileges to the sphere of the consumption of goods. From this
arises the insurmountable contradictions at the heart of the
soviet society and economy. From this arises the necessity of a
second political, anti-bureaucratic revolution, the only
historical alternative to the disintegration of the planned
economy and collective ownership by the transformation of a part
of the bureaucracy into a dominant capitalist class.
In this framework, the
direction of the politics of the CPSU is neither objectively
predetermined nor without influence in the evolution of the
countries of the world. It possesses an evident margin of
autonomy. In the face of the enlargement of commodity production
and of the expansion of the bureaucracy, this direction can
stimulate or fight these developments. Up to now, it has
accelerated them in a significant manner. It has thus sharpened
the social contradictions. Far from being an arm of the
proletarian masses (of the proletariat as a class) against
bureaucracy, as Lenin hoped and wished, the party has
transformed itself into an instrument of bureaucratic authority.
Instead of raising the proletariat to the position of direct
class dominance during the dictatorship of the proletariat, the
party has transformed itself into a bureaucratic machine
separate from the working class. The bureaucratisation of the
party is entwined with the bureaucratisation of the state to
oppress the proletariat once again.
It is evident that all these
problems are closely linked to those of the thermidor. But is
much less well known that, already by 1921, Lenin had posed the
problem of an eventual thermidor in the Soviet Union in his
notes for the 10th Conference of the party: ‘Thermidor? In
reason one has to say: it’s possible, isn’t it?
Will it arrive? We will see.’ [39]
V. The
fetishistic ideology of the bureaucracy
The ideological evolution of
the stalinist and post-stalinist bureaucracy in the USSR
corresponds in a striking manner – we would even say a
surprising manner – with the contradictory and hybrid social
reality of the USSR, with the specific overlapping of
bureaucratic despotism and of the influence of the law of value.
The bureaucracy does not have
its own ideology. It continues to support itself on a systematic
deformation of marxism as a substitute for such an ideology. But
it does not involve a fortunate or exclusively pragmatic
deformation. Cutting across the cynicism of realpolitik
which has lead the Kremlin to impose a thousand conjunctural
twists and capers on those unfortunate official ideologues, more
fundamental traits have emerged little by little.
The first of these traits is
the fetishisation of the state pushed to the extreme. In his Critique
of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right (Kritik des
Hegelschen Staatsrecht), Marx had already presented
this fetishisation as an ideological characteristic of all
bureaucracies. He did it in a penetrating and brilliant fashion,
one which is completely applicable to the soviet bureaucracy:
‘The bureaucratic mind is
through and through a Jesuitical, theological mind. The
bureaucrats are the Jesuits and theologians of the state. The
bureaucracy is la république prêtre. Since the
bureaucracy according to its essence is the state as
formalism, so too it is according to its end. The real end of
the state thus appears to the bureaucracy as an end opposed to
the state. The mind of the bureaucracy is the formal mind of
the state. It therefore makes the formal mind of the state, or
the real mindlessness of the state, a categorical imperative.
The bureaucracy asserts itself to be the final end of the
state. Because the bureaucracy makes its formal aims its
content, it comes into conflict everywhere with the real aims.
Hence it is obliged to present what is formal for the content
and the content for what is formal. The aims of the state are
transformed into aims of bureaus, or the aims of bureaus into
the aims of the state. The bureaucracy is a circle from which
no one can escape, its hierarchy is a hierarchy of knowledge.
The highest point entrusts the understanding of particulars to
the lower echelons, whereas these, on the other hand, credit
the highest with an understanding in regard to the universal;
and thus they deceive one another. The bureaucracy is the
imaginary state alongside the real state; it is the
spiritualism of the state. As a result everything has a double
meaning, one real and one bureaucratic, just as knowledge is
double, one real and one bureaucratic (and the same with the
will). A real thing, however, is treated according to its
bureaucratic essence, according to its otherworldly, spiritual
essence. The bureaucracy has the being of the state, the
spiritual being of society, in its possession; it is its
private property. The general spirit of the bureaucracy is the
secret, the mystery, preserved inwardly by means of the
hierarchy and externally as a closed corporation. To make
public the mind and the disposition of the state appears
therefore to the bureaucracy as a betrayal of its mystery.
Accordingly authority is the principle of its knowledge and
being, and the deification of authority is its mentality. But
at the very heart of the bureaucracy this spiritualism turns
into a crass materialism, the materialism of passive
obedience, of trust in authority, the mechanism of an ossified
and formalistic behaviour, of fixed principles, conceptions,
and traditions. As far as the individual bureaucrat is
concerned, the end of the state becomes his private end: a
pursuit of higher posts, the building of a career. In the
first place, he considers real life to be purely material, for
the spirit of this life has its separate existence in the
bureaucracy. Thus the bureaucrat must make life as
materialistic as possible. Secondly, real life is material for
the bureaucrat, i.e. in so far as it becomes an object of
bureaucratic action, because his spirit is prescribed for him,
his end lies outside of him, his existence is the existence of
the bureau. The state, then, exists only as various
bureau-minds whose connection consists of subordination and
dumb obedience. Real knowledge appears to be devoid of content
just as real life appears to be dead, for this imaginary
knowledge and life pass for what is real and essential. Thus
the bureaucrat must use the real state Jesuitically, no matter
whether this Jesuitism be conscious or unconscious. But given
that his antithesis is knowledge, it is inevitable that he
likewise attain to self-consciousness and, at that moment,
deliberate Jesuitism. While the bureaucracy is on one hand
this crass materialism, it manifests its crass spiritualism in
its will to do everything, i.e., in its making the will the causa
prima, for it is pure active existence which receives its
content from without; thus it can manifest its existence only
through forming and restricting this content. The bureaucrat
has the world as a mere object of his action.’ [40]
Let’s see how this applies in
practice to the soviet bureaucracy: first of all a doctrine
which denies the parasitism and the historically limited,
transient character of the state. Let’s listen to doctor L.S.
Mamut, that particularly gifted author:
‘From a retrospective point
of view the reality of the state, as can be seen only on the
scale of world history, develops a continuously more elevated
level of political liberty for the society and its social
subjects (...) According to Marx, liberty can only be created
with the help of institutions (of the state); to that end they
are fundamentally changed and, what is more important, have to
be placed under the effective control of the workers of the
new society (...) After the victory of the revolutionary
proletariat over the bourgeoisie, the liberty of society will
include the liberty of every worker. A collective
liberty which does not have as a precondition the liberty of every
associated individual is, according to Marx and Engels, simply
absurd. Society cannot liberate itself without liberating each
individual.’ [41]
With the exception of the last
two phrases, which come from Marx and Engels and not from an
ideologue of the soviet bureaucracy, this extract is
theoretically and empirically absurd. The ‘victory of the
revolutionary proletariat over the bourgeoisie’ has been a
reality in the Soviet Union for sixty eight years. Does each
soviet worker today have the freedom to create an
independent union, a political organisation or a monthly paper
without the prior approbation of an organ of the state? May he
write and distribute a pamphlet or a tract that displeases the
‘functionaries’ without censure? If he tries to do so,
isn’t he lead immediately to the commissariat whether in a
labour camp or a psychiatric hospital, and doesn’t he
immediately lose his job? Is that the liberty of the individual?
Does the soviet working class effectively control the KGB?
Where? How? When? Aren’t intelligent critics ashamed to writes
such nonsense? Where is ‘the soviet workers control’ over
the central organs of the state – the same organs of the state
that are supposed to guarantee ‘a continuously more elevated
level of political liberty for the society and its social
subjects’? This control might exist in relation to the
circulation of the metro or to the temperature of the soup in
the factory kitchen (but even that is not certain!). But such a
‘control’ exists equally under different forms in bourgeois
democracy: this is not ‘a more elevated level of political
liberty for the social subject’.
A sophist might reply:
‘political liberty’ is less important than economic liberty.
Let’s admit it. But in what way, and why, are these opposites?
And then are soviet workers free to determine the proportions of
the state economic plan, to decide the relationship between
consumption and accumulation? Are they free to criticise Gosplan
decisions in public, to propose alternative proportions in the
state’s spending, salarial or social, or the politics of
health and education? Isn’t that ‘economic freedom’? And
how can one enjoy economic liberty without enjoying political
liberty, when the state controls the means of production and
social surplus?
Is it compatible with marxism
to pretend that, even if the workers effectively control the
organs of the state, they would transform the state such that it
would guarantee ‘ever greater liberty’? Not at all. Engels
wrote:
‘In possession of the
public power and the right of taxation, the officials now
present themselves as organs of society standing above
society. The free, willing respect accorded to the organs of
the gentile constitution is not enough for them, even if they
could have it. Representatives of a power which estranges them
from society, they have to be given prestige by means of
special decrees, which invest them with a peculiar sanctity
and inviolability. The lowest police officer of the civilized
state has more “authority” than all the organs of gentile
society put together; but the mightiest prince and the
greatest statesman or general of civilization might envy the
humblest of the gentile chiefs the unforced and unquestioned
respect accorded to him. For the one stands in the midst of
society; the other is forced to pose as something outside and
above it.’ [42]
Here one is far from ‘the
state which’ from the point of view of world history
‘develops more and more liberty’ for individuals! These
lines of Engels brilliantly sum up the complete marxist theory
of bureaucracy. What’s more, Engels, writing to Bebel, said exactly
the opposite to what Mamut said concerning ‘the state as
guarantor of liberty’.
‘As long as the proletariat
still uses the state, it uses it not in the interests of
liberty, but to oppress its adversaries and, as soon as it’s
a question of liberty, the state as such ceases to exist.’ [43]
As for the difference between
the bourgeois state – and all other forms of class dominated
states – on the one hand and the proletarian state (the
dictatorship of the proletariat) as Marx and Engels had
conceived it, Lenin was still more cutting and radical. In the State
and Revolution he wrote, in referring to the Paris
commune and the dictatorship of the proletariat:
‘It is still necessary to
suppress the bourgeoisie and crush their resistance ... The
organ of suppression, however, is here the majority of the
population, and not a minority, as was always the case ... And
since the majority of people itself suppresses its oppressors,
a “special force” for suppression is no longer necessary!
In this sense, the state begins to wither away. Instead of the
special institutions of a privileged minority (privileged
officialdom, the chiefs of the standing army), the majority
itself can directly fulfil all these functions, and the more
the functions of state power are performed by the people as a
whole, the less need there is for the existence of this power
... This shows more clearly than anything else the turn from
bourgeois to proletarian democracy, from the democracy of the
oppressors to that of the oppressed classes, from the state as
a “special force” for the suppression of a particular
class to the suppression of the oppressors by the general
force of the majority of the people ...’ [44]
Lenin summed up the difference
between the bourgeois state and the dictatorship of the
proletariat in these succinct and radical terms: ‘Soviet power
is a new type of state, without bureaucracy, without police,
without a standing army.’ [45]
We see yet again all that
separates the bureaucratic workers’ state and the power of
councils as envisaged by Marx, Engels and Lenin. The irony is
that if anyone was to publish and distribute Lenin’s quote
today in the USSR, they would receive a sentence of five to ten
years of forced labour in the gulag for the crime of
‘anti-soviet agitation’ or of ‘defamation of the soviet
authorities’. Worse still, he might be subjected to years of
internment in a psychiatric hospital brainwashed by medication.
Effectively one would have to be mad – as mad as Lenin – to
imagine a soviet state without bureaucrats, without police and
without a standing army ... The fetishism of the state sometimes
passes beyond belief: the bureaucracy’s ideologues tranquilly
envisage the maintenance of the secret police, i.e. the KGB, in
a ‘fully developed’(sic) communist society without
state: ‘the state withers away but the organs remain’! How,
indeed, to foresee its own disappearance as a distinct and
privileged social group without denying itself now? One could
not find better proof than this that the ideologues of the
bureaucracy are, in the last analysis, the ideologues of the
police.
But in the ideology of the
bureaucracy the fetishism of the state is combined, at the same
time, in a bizarre and significant manner with classical commodity
fetishism, a characteristic of all commodity producing
societies (partial or general). Marx demonstrated that commodity
production only exists as a function of the private character of
work, thus of private property (once again: partial or general).
No, the stalinist and post-stalinist ideologues reply. The law
of value rules in the USSR as a function of ‘objective
necessity’: it’s an ‘objective law’.
Borrowing a formula, in any
case shortened, from Engels, and refilling it with a content
completely different from Engel’s, they add: liberty can only
be the recognition of necessity. But with this formula, Engels
was explicitly referring to the ‘law of nature’. For
stalinist and post-stalinist ideologues the ‘law of value’
thus has the force of a ‘law of nature’, while for Marx and
Engels the law was truly neither ‘natural’ nor eternal, but
strictly linked to particular social conditions, limited in
time, those precisely of societies in which producers work
separately from one another because of private ownership, and
don’t enter into mutual relations with each other except by
the exchange of products from their private work.
The hybrid combination of the
fetishisation of the state and the fetishisation of commodities
in the ideology of the bureaucracy, takes in its turn the
specific form of justification of its own role and of the
function of the bureaucracy in itself. The bureaucracy
‘uses’ (the young Marx said: petrifies) the ‘objective
laws’ to direct the economy. The despotic state manipulates
‘the law of value’, that’s to say it violates it at every
step. But at the same time bureaucratic planning has to bend
before ‘the material interests’ of the producers (in fact
that of the bureaucrats), and cannot base itself on the priority
realisation of democratic needs defined by the workers in terms
of ‘use values’, because ‘the law of value prohibits
it’. It will reign, then, despite the sovereignty of the
state. Sometimes the arbitrary nature of bureaucratic management
is legitimated by this, sometimes it is its wasteful
disfunctionality, which will be in fact independent of the will
and the action of the bureaucracy.
‘One oughtn’t to go to
the other extreme: if commodity production prevails, and with
it the anarchy of the market, the law of value will act in a
spontaneous manner, production for an unknown free market will
be inevitable, given the regulatory role of this law, etc.
Spontaneity is prevented by the socialist state, since it
attempts to restrain the negative sides [!] of commodity-money
relations and to subordinate their instruments [?] to
consciously planned goals. Thanks to the theory of
marxism-leninism and from the practice of the construction of
socialism and communism, the great economic potential of the
socialist state as subject and organising force of the
economic mechanism has been discovered [!] and demonstrated.
It would, however, be an error to believe that in socialism
the determination of quantity [of the measure?] of work and
consumption depends solely [!] on the state. To an important
extent this function is fulfilled by the law of value.’ [46]
According to Marx, the law of
value imposes itself in a market economy in an objective manner,
on the backs of men and women, and acts independently of their
will. It determines in the medium term – but not by day to day
– the value of commodities and thus the value of the commodity
of ‘labour power’, in so far as the latter is a commodity.
In socialist society, are the resources available for the
producers consumption determined by their conscious decision to
devote let’s say 75% of production to consumer goods? No,
replies our not very red professor: the socialist state (and
what of the associated producers?) isn’t free to determine by
itself the size of these resources: ‘to an important extent’
these function is fulfilled by the law of value.
Thus labour force is still a
commodity! If not, how else could it have a value determined by
‘the law of value’? But if labour force is a commodity, in
the same way as the means of production, how can ‘the
socialist state’ prevent ‘the law of value’ – an
objective law, independent of human will – from determining
the values of all commodities, and thus the dynamics of
economic growth? It’s because the ‘socialist state’ can
‘restrain’ this law! If this pure gibberish has any sense,
it’s that it demonstrates that the disorder in the
‘theory’ of the bureaucracy is of the same measure as the
disorder in its practical management. This all ends up with the
revisionist concept that the state survives, not just in
socialist society but even in a ‘not entirely achieved’
communist society, and this despite the complete disappearance
of classes. What is this strange state for? ‘The withering
away of the state will depend in the first place on the success
with which the rest of capitalism is eliminated from the
consciousness of man.’ [47]
In other terms: an apparatus of
repression is necessary – ‘groups of armed men’ – to
exclusively impose ideological discipline (monolithism)! The
police restrict themselves to policing ideas, since they have
nothing else to do. But, even so, they must survive to fulfil
this ‘vital’ function. Isn’t it evident that we are in the
presence of an ideology of self-justification which reflects the
material existence of the bureaucracy as an apparatus, that
appropriates for itself the exercise of functions that society
formerly exercised without a special apparatus, which could be
exercised in the same manner tomorrow except that it isn’t
‘authorised’ to exercise it because the bureaucracy needs to
survive at any price?
The full significance of the
anti-bureaucratic political revolution, and its objective
necessity, cannot be grasped without understanding both the
objective role of the bureaucracy and the objective function of
socialist democracy in the USSR. It is not about applying some
‘ideal norms’. It is about the socio-economic necessities
resulting from the inherent contradictions of soviet society.
When the state takes control of
all the major means of production, appropriates and centrally
distributes the social surplus, the question of the control of
both these things becomes decisive for the dynamics of society.
This question implies a redistribution of the social surplus
between the three great funds mentioned above (the A, B, C in
section IV, Translator’s note). While in the absence
of effective democracy in the councils, the state is driven to
carry out its management without reference to the needs and
preferences of the great mass of producers and consumers, which
are both clearly recognised and expressed, social despotism
(that’s to say oppression) and economic dysfunction are inevitable.
For this reason, the
arbitrary-despotic character of the centralised economic
allocation in the Soviet Union does not reflect the
‘essence’ of collective ownership and still less the
‘essence’ of the imperatives of a planned economy. The
bureaucracy may apply ‘reforms’ with the aim of correcting
this arbitrary character. It may reapply supplementary doses of
market economy. But the bureaucratic centralism remains no less
despotic and wasteful; it is condemned to remain so. There is
only one alternative to arbitrary bureaucracy: a system of
planning and management in which the mass of workers centrally
allocate resources and democratically determine priorities
themselves. Such a system demands that the masses
themselves articulate their needs as producers, consumers and
citizens, in other words that they become the masters of their
conditions of work and life, that they progressively liberate
themselves from despotism, from the bureaucratic diktat
and from that of the market (the tyranny of the wallet).
It is only in this way that one
can, in the immediate future, beat the irresponsibility and
incompetence of the bureaucracy. The satisfactory solution of
relations between production and needs signifies democratic
centralism, that’s to say the auto-centralised administration
of the economy and the state, planned and realised by the
workers themselves. [48] This
is not possible except with the progressive restriction
(but not the immediate abolition) not only of commodity
production but also of the bureaucracy, in the framework of the
socialist democracy of councils.
Footnotes
1.
Friedrich Engels, Anti-Dühring, p.168, Marx-Engels-Werke,
MEW, vol.20, our own translation.
2.
Friedrich Engels, The Origins of the Family, Private
Property and the State, MEW, vol.21,
pp.165-166.
3.
Friedrich Engels, Anti-Dühring, ibid.,
p.169.
4.
Karl Marx, The German Ideology, Éditions
Sociales, Paris 1966, pp.51-53.
5.
Leon Trotsky, The Revolution Betrayed, Paris,
Grasset, 1937, pp.70, 131-132.
6.
Friedrich Engels, The Origins of the Family, Private
Property and the State, ibid., p.165.
7.
Rosa Luxemburg, The Russian Revolution, Paris,
Maspero, 1964, p.71.
8.
Ibid., p.70.
9.
Friedrich Engels, A Contribution to the Critique of
Political Economy, Selected Works in 2 vols.,
vol.1, p.390, Éditions du Progrès, 1955.
10.
Karl Marx, Critique of the Gotha Programme , MEW,
vol.19, p.20.
11.
Karl Marx, The German Ideology, op.
cit., pp.53-54.
12.
For example, Fédosseiev et al., Marxist-Leninist
teachings on Socialism and Actuality, Moscow 1975,
p.97.
13.
V.I. Lenin, The State and Revolution, in Lenin,
Works, vol.25, Paris-Moscow, Éditions Sociales
– Édition de Progrès, 1971, p.502. It should be noted that
Lenin is speaking of the quantity of work and not of the
quantity and quality of work.
14.
‘We often say that our republic is a socialist republic. Does
that signify that we have already realised socialism, eliminated
classes and the state – because the realisation of socialism
signifies the withering away of the state? Or is it that it
signifies that classes, the state, etc. survive under socialism?
It is evident that it doesn’t signify that.’ (J.V. Stalin, Letter
to Kouchtyssev of the 28th December 1928, in Werke,
Vol.11, p.278. Our translation from the German.
15.
George Lukacs, Letter to Alberto Carocci, in Forum,
Austrian monthly for cultural liberty, 10th year, Hefte 115-116,
117, 1963. Here cited from Lukacs, Schriften zur
Ideologie und Politik, Luchterhand Verlag, 1967, p.661.
16.
Trotsky, The Third International after Lenin,
Paris, PUF, 1969, vol.1, p.188.
17.
Cf. Marx, Forms which precede capitalist production, in
Grundrisse, pp.471-514, on the role of communal
property as an obstacle to capitalist relations of production
and even to the production of exchange values in the villages.
‘Its first task [great industry’s] is to incorporate the
country, in all its amplitude, into production not of use values
but of exchange values.’ The most significant passages of Marx
on this subject are to be found in Capital
vol.1, in MEW, vol.23, pp.378-379.
18.
We cannot analyse Soviet wage labour in detail here. The concept
of ‘wages’ takes account of two phenomena (processes) which
combine under capitalism, but not in pre-capitalist or
post-capitalist societies (or at least not with the same
dynamic). On the one hand, it signifies indirect access to
consumer goods, only in exchange for money and limited by that. In
this sense the Russian worker is certainly still a wage
worker. But wage labour also signifies the existence of a labour
market, the constraint of producers in selling their labour
power in this market, and the determination of the price of
‘labour power’ by supply and demand in this market, a price
which oscillates around an objective social value of the price
of such ‘merchandise’ . For this to happen the wage labourer
must have been deprived of access to the means of production as
well as from the means of subsistence. This no longer exists in
the Soviet Union, to the extent that the ‘right to work’ is
guaranteed not only in the constitution but also in practice.
Labour power (with significant exceptions) is thus not a
commodity and the wage labourer is not a wage labourer in the
capitalist sense.
19.
This constitutes the fundamental theoretical error of
Castoriadis and others who pretend that the armaments sector has
attained a complete autonomy in the USSR. Cornèlius
Castoriadis, Devant la Guerre 1, Farard, 1981.
20.
We ignore the unrealisable ‘special case’ where the USSR
achieves such a stunning advance in average labour productivity vis-à-vis
international capitalism that it will be able to liberate itself
in a ‘purely economic’ fashion from the law of value. In
this case, it would become a kingdom of abundance, that’s to
say a communist society where there will not be a place for a
‘new leading class’.
21.
Cf. our essay among others Ten
theses on transitional society, in Probleme des
Sozialismus und der Uebergangsgesellshaft, Suhrkamp,
1972, also The
Laws of Motion of the Soviet Economy, in Critique
number 12, 1974. We have expressed this same fundamental point
of view in the chapter given over to the soviet economy in Traité
d’Économie Marxiste, written in 1960 and published
for the first time in 1962.
22.
Cf. our polemic with Paul M. Sweezy in Monthly Review,
and with The Alternative by Rudolf Bahro. The
formula ‘Bureaucratic state’ doesn’t have any meaning. The
state is ‘bureaucratic’ by definition! It represents an
apparatus separate from society. Everything depends on the class
nature of the state and thus of the bureaucracy. There are
despotic bureaucracies (those under the Asiatic mode of
production), bureaucracies of slavery, feudal and semi-feudal
bureaucracies (these last in absolute monarchies), bourgeois
bureaucracies, workers’ bureaucracies, etc. Apparently, the
soviet bureaucracy is still a workers’ bureaucracy, which
doesn’t ‘justify’ or in any way soften its parasitic
characteristics, its enormous waste of social resources or its
crimes. But a ‘bureaucratised bureaucracy’ is a formula
which has no meaning.
23.
The parallel between the complicated, hierarchic and extremely
formalised system of state offices in traditional China on the
one hand and the nomenklatura in the soviet bureaucracy
on the other (which are both based on examination, in the case
of the USSR by examinations in the theory and practice of
‘marxism-leninism’) jumps out at one and is very significant
sociologically.
24.
‘(...) In part because in each previous mode of production the
principal proprietor of the social surplus ... the slaver, the
feudal lord, the state, for example the oriental despot,
represent the idle rich’. Marx, Capital,
vol.III, MEW, vol.XXV, p.343.
25.
All the layers of the bureaucracy – not only the imagined
‘political’ bureaucracy – which have no direct relations
with the means of production, and can only ‘command’ in an
indirect manner with orders, are much less inclined to abandon
the centrally allocated economy, the imperative nature of the
plan and the collective ownership of the means of production.
But this does not at all mean that they are less corrupt or less
interested in their own enrichment, including the private
accumulation of gold, foreign goods, jewellery, works of art,
Swiss bank accounts, etc. than the technocratic and
administrative layers of the bureaucracy (at the level of the
factory).
26.
Different observers of Soviet daily life, notably the
philosopher and satirist Alexandre Zinoviev (cf. Alexandre
Zinoviev, Le Communisme comme Réalité,
l’Age d’Homme, Paris, 1981) but also, unfortunately, the
oppositional revolutionary socialist Ticktin, affirm that
stability in the Soviet Union rests on a tacit connivance
between the bureaucracy and the workers (Ticktin, Critique
no.12, pp.132-135, and p.129). The weakness of this thesis has
been demonstrated by the events in Poland in the summer of 1980,
and the tenacity of the Polish workers in obtaining greater
social and economic justice. Ultimately it is a thesis
apologetic of the ‘really existing’ conditions, just like
the parallel thesis on the pretended ‘consensus’ between
capitalists and the ‘silent majority’ in the west. The
‘rational heart’ of this thesis is unravelled by the fact
that in the ‘private’ sector (the black and grey sectors of
the economy), salaries in the USSR can be effectively six or
seven times higher than in the state sector. But, in the Soviet
Union, that is only possible precisely because these sectors are
marginal and have no decisive weight at the heart of the economy
(on this subject ridiculous exaggerations circulate in the
west). There isn’t a single material basis to allow the real
average salary to be six or seven times higher than it is today
in the USSR. Cf. Marx’s observations on the role of
slave production at the heart of capitalism, Grundrisse,
p.368, German edition.
27.
Bettelheim, Les Luttes de Classe en Union Soviétique,
analysis and details of workers’ struggles which happened in
the Soviet Union in the twenties and thirties. But this
doesn’t at all prove that this struggle finished in the
resurrection of a labour market, that is the
transformation of the proletariat into ‘free wage workers’,
that is by an economic defeat of the workers. What it
proves is the grave political and social defeat of the
soviet working class. But this is a thesis that the soviet left
opposition – unknown by Bettleheim – and later on the
Trotskyist movement defended for over forty five years. This
defeat was precisely the soviet thermidor. Like the
thermidor of the French revolution, it retained the economic
foundation of society created in the course of the revolution,
instead of destroying it.
28.
For orthodox Maoists a large dose of ignorance and cynicism are
needed in order to accuse the Chinese proletariat, and certain
factions of the Chinese bureaucracy after the ‘Chinese
cultural revolution’ of economism, because they demanded a
modest increase in wages. The proletariat had lived for a decade
with stagnant monetary wages and declining real wages. At the
same time, the ruling layers of the bureaucracy – here
including Mao’s faction in the restrictive sense of the term
– lived in abundance, having enormous privileges, with villas,
private cinemas, private gardens and swimming pools, and heaps
of private servants in their luxury villas. This cynicism
wasn’t only shared by the ruling clique of the People’s
republic, but also by the most important Maoist intellectuals
outside China ... A cynicism which cannot be ‘excused’ but
by the flagrant ignorance of real conditions. But for the
intellectuals it isn’t an excuse, above all because this naïve
ignorance shows itself twice: firstly in relation to the soviet
reality, then in relation to the Chinese reality.
29.
Ernest Mandel, Traité d’Économie Marxiste,
Paris, collection 10/18, 1969, vol.4, pp.84-149.
30.
Cf. also A Bagdarassov, S. Pervouchine, Productivité du
Travail, Réserves pour la Croissance, Kommunist
no.2, 1983.
‘A major cause of the
quantitatively and qualitatively poor statistics of economic
growth comes from the fact that in place of a real economy of
work on a non-equivalent basis, an exchange is produced between
living work and dead work, objectified, in the terms of
which each new pace towards the growth of productivity of work
based on a larger expenditure for objectified work, is not
compensated by expenditure on living work in the economy’.
31.
Karl Marx, The Civil War in France, in Oeuvres
Choisies in 2 vols., op. cit., p.555.
32.
Ibidem, p.512.
33.
Lenin, The State and Revolution, op.
cit., p.252.
34.
Lenin, Werke, vol.32, p.7. Alexandre Zimine (Le
Stalinisme et son ”socialisme réel“, Paris, La Brèche,
1982) presents an overwhelming indictment against the
revisionist thesis of a ‘socialism’ that would go hand in
hand with the persistent survival of diverse social classes.
35.
Relating to this, cf. the article by W.S. Semionov, the chief
editor of the soviet journal Voprossi Philosophii,
The problem of contradictions under socialism, in no.7,
1982, and A. Butenko, The contradiction of the development
of socialism as a social order, no.10, 1982.
36.
A. Butenko, op. cit.
37.
George Lukacs, Lettre à Carocci, op. cit.,
p.658.
38.
Ibidem, p.674.
39.
V.I. Lenin, Sochineniya (Complete Works
in Russian), vol.43, p.403 of the fifth edition.
40.
Karl Marx, Kritik des Hegelschen Staatsrecht, MEW,
vol.1, pp.248-250.
41.
L.S. Mamut, Aspects Socio-Philosophiques de la Doctrine
Marxiste de l’État, in Voprossi Philosophii
no.2, 1982. The citation of Marx is in MEW
vol.XX, p.273.
42.
Friedrich Engels, The Origins of the Family, Private
Property and the State, op. cit.,
p.166.
43.
Friedrich Engels, Lettre à Bebel du 18-28 mars 1875,
in MEW, vol.34, p.129.
44.
Lenin, The State and Revolution, op.
cit. pp. 194-195.
45.
Lenin, Sämtliche Werke, first edition, vol.22,
p.390.
46.
Professor A.I. Malych, Fragen der Ökonomischen Theorie in
Friedrich Engels Anti-Duhring, in Marx-Engels
Jahrbuch 2, Dietz-Verlag, Berlin 1979, pp.103-104.
47.
Grundlagen der Marxistischen Philosophie
(German translation of a soviet work), Dietz-Verlag, Berlin
1959, p.584.
48.
Experience has shown that without political pluralism, that’s
to say without an effective system (and not only a formal one)
of different political groupings, free elections and the
possibility to elect and recall the leaders from the highest
posts are impossible in an already consolidated workers’
state. Cf. the theses adopted on Dictatorship
of the proletariat and socialist democracy by the XII
Congress of the IV International.
|