Paul Sweezy has finally started
to discuss the Marxist tradition – which, he acknowledges, is
by and large represented by Trotskyism – with regard to the
Russian Revolution and its subsequent fate. True, he still
rejects that interpretation. But he is at least ready to discuss
it, and his first comments contained in Monthly Review
(October 1978) are of a provisional nature. By answering them an
the main challenges they raise, we hope to be able to contribute
to a constructive debate – both with Paul Sweezy, the editors
of Monthly Review, and the readers of that
magazine – about what remains a key issue for the future of
the international labor movement.
Sweezy takes us to task for
repeating – forty years after Trotsky’s analysis of 1939 –
the thesis that the Soviet Union’s fate and, therefore, the
question of the nature of the bureaucracy isn’t settled yet.
Trotsky, Sweety claims, made sense because he posed the question
in a short-term perspective. Mandel, he continues, just repeats
Trotsky without realizing that the very time-scale he is talking
about undermines the credibility of the theory.
The point Sweety seems to miss
is that what is involved in the problems Trotsky posed was not a
question of time-scale, but the basic trends of development of
the contemporary world. This becomes clear if we reproduce again
the two passages from Trotsky’s article The USSR in War,
quoted by Sweezy:
If, however, it is conceded
that the present war will provoke not revolution but a decline
of the proletariat, then there remains another alternative:
the further decay of monopoly capitalism, its further fusion
with the state and the replacement of democracy wherever it
still remained by a totalitarian regime. The inability of the
proletariat to take into its hands the leadership of society
could actually lead under these conditions to the growth of a
new exploiting class from the Bonapartist fascist bureaucracy.
And again:
If contrary to all
probabilities the October Revolution fails during the course
of the present war, or immediately thereafter, to find its
continuation in any of the advanced countries; and if, on the
contrary, the proletariat is thrown back everywhere and on all
fronts – then we should doubtlessly have to revise our
conceptions of the present epoch and its driving forces. In
that case it would be a question not of slapping a copybook
label on the USSR or the Stalinist gang but of re-evaluating
the world historic perSpective for the next decades if not
centuries: Have we entered the epoch of social revolution and
socialist society, or on the contrary the epoch of the
declining society of totalitarian bureaucracy?
Now, Sweezy stresses, there has
been no new victory of a proletarian revolution in an advanced
country, either in the course of the Second World War or
immediately thereafter. This is undoubtedly true. But Sweezy
forgets the second part of the question posed by Trotsky: Has
there been a “decline of the proletariat”? In numbers? In
skill? In levels of organization or militancy? How can one argue
such a thesis after May 1968, which saw three times as many
strikers occupying factories in France as in the previous record
level of June 1936? After autumn 1969 in Italy, which saw eight
times as many workers occupying factories as in the famous
strike wave of November 1920? After the first six months of 1976
in Spain, which saw three times as many strikers as at the
height of the revolution in 1936? This is besides Britain,
Japan, the smaller European countries, Portugal, and elsewhere,
where the working-class struggles in the last decade have far
outdistanced their highest prewar levels.
Has the proletariat been
“thrown back everywhere and on all fronts”? Has (bourgeois)
democracy, wherever it still remained in 1939-40, been replaced
by a totalitarian regime? Again, obviously not. So it is not out
of routinism or exaggerated respect for “the master” that we
still stick to the terms of Trotsky’s 1939 thesis. We come to
this conclusion because we base ourselves upon a sober balance
sheet of what has happened in the last forty years.
Indeed, the question of the
secular trend is and remains that posed by Trotsky in his 1939
article. However, the time-scale was obviously wrong. And
because of this, an “intermediary” variant was left out,
which explains precisely why the question has not yet been
decided by history. There was a rise of world revolution during
and after the Second World War. There was an upsurge and not a
further decline of working-class struggles. But because of the
effects on the average consciousness of the working class of
twenty years of defeats of revolution, this rise was only
partial and it could therefore be channeled in the main by
political force of, or originating from, the bureaucracies of
the traditional labor movement (British Labor Party, French,
Italian, Greek Communist parties, Titoism, Maoism, etc.).
In some semi-colonial countries
this did not prevent new victorious socialist revolutions, even
if they were bureaucratically distorted from the start
(Yugoslavia, China, Vietnam). In the imperialist countries on
the other hand, where the bourgeoisie is much more powerful and
hence a much higher level of consciousness and leadership of the
proletariat are necessary for a revolutionary victory, it led to
the emasculation of the anti-capitalist potential of the mass
struggles, but not without the working class having gained new
and important reforms inside bourgeois society, and having
prevented the bourgeoisie from resorting to open dictatorships.
For reasons we cannot go into
here, there then followed a new period of accelerated economic
growth in the imperialist countries, leading to a new growth of
the proletariat. This in turn laid the basis for a new
revolutionary potential in the West – the May 1968 explosion
being its first expression. In other words, there was no
“retreat of the proletariat on all fronts” but a rise,
insufficient to overthrow capitalism, but sufficient to prevent
a slide into “the declining society of totalitarian
bureaucracy.” But after the “long wave of expansion” of
postwar capitalism, the turn of the late 1960s relentlessly
inaug urated a new period of profound and prolonged crisis which
restates the problem in Trotsky’s terms.
Let us add that Trotsky’s
1939 article was only a first sketch of the historical
perspective in relation to the Second World War. In a more
programmatic document – his real political testament – The
Manifesto of the Emergency Conference of the Fourth
International (May 1940), Trotsky poses the problem of
the time-scale in a much more realistic way:
Will not the revolution be
betrayed this time too, inasmuch as there are two
Internationnls in the service of imperialism, while the
genuine revolutionary elements constitute a tiny minority? ...
In order to answer this question correctly, it is necessary to
pose it correctly. Naturally, this or that uprising may end
and surely will end in defeat, owing to the immaturity of the
revolutionary leadership. But it is not the question of a
single uprising. It is the question of an entire revolutionary
epoch.
It is necessary to prepare
for long years, if not decades, of war, uprisings, brief
interludes of truce, new wars, and new uprisings. A young
revolutionary party must base itself on this perspective.
History will provide it with enough opportunities and
possibilities to test itself, to accumulate experience, and to
mature. (Documents of the Fourth International,
pp.345-346)
In that sense, the postwar
time-scale Sweezy opposes to Trotsky’s thesis, is the very one
in which Trotsky envisaged it in a more programmatic and less
propagandistic formulation of the question. But, one may ask,
what has all this to do with the class nature of the Soviet
bureaucracy? In answering this, we are at the historical heart
of “Trotskyism,” i.e., contemporary revolutionary Marxism.
Workers and poor peasants, Trotskyism holds, should take power
wherever the opportunity presents itself. In the epoch of
imperialism the opportunity might present itself in a less
developed country before it occurs in the more advanced ones.
But the taking of power (and the suppression of private
ownership of the means of production) is only one necessary but
in and of itself insufficient precondition for the building of
socialism. This process can only be successfully achieved on an
international scale. (It should of course be initiated wherever
power is wrung from the capitalists.)
Stalinism, the victory of the
bureaucracy in the Soviet Union, is the result of partial
defeats of world revolution. World revolution did not spread to
the advanced countries. But neither was it defeated to the point
where capitalism could be restored in the Soviet Union (the
imperialists tried hard to achieve that, in 1918-21, in 1941-44,
and again, although less directly, in 1948-51). The final fate
of the USSR depends upon the outcome of the worldwide struggle
between capital and labor. If the world proletariat is
decisively defeated, then the bureaucracy will become a ruling
class (whether a new one or a capitalist one is another
question). If, on the other hand, the socialist revolution
triumphs in the West or the political revolution triumphs in
Eastern Europe, then it will not take the Soviet proletariat
long to overthrow bureaucratic rule in the USSR before the
bureaucracy has had the chance to become such a ruling class.
We stress: “or the political
revolution triumphs in Eastern Europe.” For Sweezy’s other
argument – the idea that the working class of the Stalinist
countries accepts the regime, albeit grudgingly – is
contradicted by spectacular events to which he does not refer at
all: the workers’ uprising in the German Democratic Republic
of 1953, the Hungarian revolution of 1956, the Prague spring of
1968, and the repeated mass uprisings of the Polish workers.
Indeed, has not the “abstract” idea of political revolution,
put forward by Trotsky and the Fourth International some 45
years ago, been given a real “concrete” content by these
historic events?
II
The hypothesis that the Soviet
bureaucracy is a new ruling class does not correspond to a
serious analysis of the real development and the real
contradictions of Soviet society and economy in the last fifty
years. Such a hypothesis must imply, from the point of view of
historical materialism, that a new exploitative mode of
production has emerged in that country. If this were so, we
would be confronted, for the first time in history, with a
“ruling class” whose general behavior and private interests
(which of course dictate that behavior) run counter to the needs
and inner logic of the existing socio-economic system. Indeed,
one of the main characteristics of the Soviet economy is the
impossibility of reconciling the needs of planning, of
optimizing economic growth (not from an “absolute” point of
view, but from within the logic of the system itself) with the
material self-interest of the bureaucracy.
All the successive economic
reforms introduced in the USSR under the bureaucracy – from
the re-introduction of enterprise-based cost accountancy
(khozrazhot) under Stalin, to Khrushchev’s sovnarkhoz
experiment, to Liberman’s projected use of profit as an
indicator for overall economic performance, to Kosygin’s
introduction of “mixed indicators” for measuring that
performance – have been designed to overcome that
contradiction, but without lasting success. One can easily
explain this apparent paradox by stressing the parasitic nature
of the bureaucracy which acts contrary to the logic of the
system. One can also add that social planning can function
smoothly only under management by associated producers,
materially interested in a “social dividend” and not in
separate distinctive gains which pit factory against factory,
town against town, branch against branch, and region against
region. But all this precisely implies that the bureaucracy –
which seeks such particular gains – is not a new ruling class,
running a sell-reproducing new mode of production, but a cancer
on a society in transition between capitalism and socialism.
Bureaucratic management is not only increasingly wasteful. It
also prevents the system of the planned economy, based upon
socialized property, from operating effectively. And this
undeniable fact is in itself incompatible with the
characterization of the bureaucracy as a ruling class and with
the USSR as a new “exploitative mode of production” whose
“laws of motion” have never been specified.
In the second place, we would
be confronted, again for the first time in history, with a
ruling class without the capacity to perpetuate itself through
the operation of the socio-economic system itself. There is no
guarantee for a bureaucrat that he or she will remain a
bureaucrat. There is even less guarantee that his or her sons
and daughters will remain bureaucrats. We agree that vertical
mobility in Soviet society – one of the main social safety
valves under Stalin – has significantly decreased during the
last decades. The “gerontocracy” of the Presidium is
symbolic of what is happening in all Soviet society. The
“security of tenure” of the bureaucrats has undoubtedly
increased. But this only leads to increasing social tension
(e.g., pressure for access to higher education), and not to a
real solution to the problem of the bureaucrats’ inability to
guarantee the permanence of their position of power and
privilege. Moreover, these positions continue to be tied
essentially to particular functions and depend upon political
decisions (e.g., the famous nomenklatura) and not to a
specific role in the process of social production. Hence the
bureaucrats’ pressure to obtain permanent ties with specific
factories, enterprises, trusts (i.e., to restore private
property in the economic sense of the word before restoring it
in the juridical sense). Hence the consistent pressure of large
layers of the bureaucracy to gain a qualitatively higher degree
of autonomy at factory or branch level (i.e., to escape the iron
framework of a centralized plan). Hence their tendency toward
private capital accumulation, through bribes, corruption,
“grey” and black market operations, hoarding of foreign
currency and gold, etc. Hence also the trend towards a growing
“symbiosis” with their counterparts in the West, including
the establishment of bank accounts in Western banks (especially
visible in the “Peoples’ Democracies”).
All this points in the
direction of the potential emergence of a “new ruling class”
– not a “new one” but a good old capitalist one, based
upon private property. But before this process can come to
fruition, two formidable obstacles have to be overcome: the
resistance of the working class, which would tend to lose in the
course of such a restoration that which it values most in the
present set-up (in fact, probably the only thing which it
values): guaranteed job security, i.e.. the right to work, full
employment, and, flowing from that. a much less hectic work
tempo than in the West; and the resistance of key sectors of the
state apparatus (note the way Tito clamped down upon the
Yugoslav “billionaires” in the early seventies, when the
danger of “restoration” became real). So to say that a new
ruling class exists and rules misreads the real social struggles
occurring in these countries. It assumes as already decided in
the past a struggle whose outcome is still open.
In the third plate, we would be
confronted, likewise for the first time in history, with a
“ruling class” representative of a “mode of production”
whose “overthrow” would leave the basic economic structure
intact. In a well-known passage of volume 3 of Capital,
Marx writes that each mode of production is characterized by a
specific form of appropriation of the social surplus product.
Now in the USSR, the social surplus product is appropriated in a
dual form: in the form of use values, inasmuch as it is composed
in its major part of additional equipment and raw materials; and
in the form of commodities, inasmuch as it is composed in its
minor part of luxury goods (and special services) bought by the
bureaucracy with its privileged income. But after the overthrow
of the bureaucratic dictatorship, this dual form of
appropriation of the social surplus product would not change –
if only because the Soviet workers will certainly not transform
the means of production into commodities (which would mean
restoring capitalism!); but they will also be unable to suppress
the commodity aspect of the nature of consumer goods rapidly (a
new revolution in the USSR would not permit the building of
socialism in one country). Likewise, neither the suppression of
the private ownership of the means of production, nor
centralized planning, nor the state monopoly of foreign trade
would be changed by such a revolution (which we therefore prefer
to call a political one). If one assembles all these factors,
one obviously gets an economic structure which remains basically
unchanged.
True, there will be a radical
change in the modus operandi of the system. The mass of
producers will get a decisive say about what is produced and how
it should be produced. Social inequality will be radically
reduced. The enormous waste caused by bureaucratic mismanagement
will cease. The organization of work and its hierarchical
structure will he radically overhauled. But the above- sketched
structure itself – the specific form of appropriation of the
social surplus product – remains basically the same.
In the fourth place, the
hypothesis of the bureaucracy’s being a new ruling class leads
to the conclusion that, for the first time in history, we are
confronted with a “ruling class” which does not exist as a
class before it actually rules. Where does it come from? Sweezy
answers: “The new exploiting class develops out of the
conditions created by the revolution itself.” But this really
begs the question. Serial classes are groups of human beings
engaged in specific relations emanating from the process of
production (“relations of production”). Social
transformations can transform them; but they cannot create them
ex nihilo. In reality, a consistent theory of a “new
exploiting class” in the Soviet Union only makes sense if one
assumes that sectors of the working class (the labor bureaucracy
and labor aristocracy) and of the intelligentsia (the petty
bourgeoisie and higher state functionaries) were potentially a
new ruling class even before they “take power,” i.e., before
“the revolution.” [1]
But formidable consequences, involving practically all aspects
of the contemporary class struggle throughout the world, and a
revision of all the constituent elements of Marxist theory,
arise from such an assumption. And without that assumption, the
notion of a “new ruling class” having arisen “out of the
historical process” becomes utterly absurd – after all, the
bureaucracy took power; how can a “non-existent” social
layer take power?
III
The idea that the Soviet
bureaucracy (like the trade-union bureaucracy in the West) has
not cut its umbilical cord with the working class, and that its
specific interests and political decisions can be seen within
the framework of that special parasitic-relationship with the
proletariat, leads to the conclusion that the class struggle in
the capitalist countries continues to be a bi-polar process:
capital versus labor (with the bureaucracy operating by and
large as “labor lieutenants of capital”).
The idea that the Soviet
bureaucracy is a new ruling class and the unavoidable conclusion
that the Communist parties not in power can be seen – at least
as far as their central apparatuses are concerned – as the
nucleus of a potential new exploiting class, implies of
necessity the complete revision of that way of looking at the
whole of twentieth-century history. The class struggle now
becomes a tri-polar affair: “capital versus labor versus the
potential new exploiting class.”
This is not simply a question
of modifying historical analysis (which in and of itself would
already be hair-raising and, at least so far as the evidence we
possess is concerned, an impossible task). It has political
implications of the greatest and gravest magnitude. We are then
left only with the choice between two evils, both of which lead
to conclusions which would pit consistent advocates of the
theory of a “new exploiting class” squarely against the
struggle of the international working class for emancipation.
For there are indeed only two possible ways of looking at that
alleged new “exploiting class.” Either it is, globally and
essentially, progressive compared to the capitalist class, i.e.,
it stands in the same relation to the bourgeoisie as the
bourgeoisie stood toward the semi-feudal aristocracy before and
during the bourgeois revolutions. Such a hypothesis would of
course be perfectly consistent with a sharp critique of its
exploitative character. But it would mean that in all
straightforward conflicts between the bourgeoisie and the
“potential new class,” one would have to give the same kind
of “critical support” to the “new class” which the Communist
Manifesto envisages for the revolutionary bourgeoisie.
And one would then have to restrict – at least partially, if
not completely – anti-bureaucratic struggles of the working
class so as not to hinder the victory of the “progressive”
bureaucracy over the reactionary bourgeoisie.
The very idea of a socialist
revolution and a conquest of power by the working class would
become at least questionable. Granted: one could say that
decadent capitalism could lead either to socialism or to the
establishment of a new class system, progressive compared to
capitalism. But in that c ase all victorious revolutions which
have occurred up till now would then have to be re-characterized
as “bureaucratic revolutions” and not proletarian ones.
Then, the allegation that the idea of a direct transition from
capitalism to socialism was a utopian conceptual error by Marx
and Marxists alike would become rather credible, to say the
least.
If the “new ruling class”
is progressive compared to capitalism, this would imply that
class society, contrary to what Marx thought, had not exhausted
its progressive potential with the rise of capitalism; that a
new and momentous development of the productive forces –
leading in the long run to a broader development of the
“social individual,” i.e., of human freedom – was still
possible without abolishing class society. Socialism would then
become merely a moral preference, not a historical necessity to
avoid barbarism and the decline of human civilization.
So, although starting by
damning the bureaucracy as new exploiters, bloodsuckers, deadly
enemies of the working class and of human freedom, etc., etc.
– and, undoubtedly, 99 percent of the real motivation for any
self-proclaimed Marxist’s calling the bureaucracy a new ruling
class stems from such understandable moral indignation rather
than cool scientific analysis – one would paradoxically end up
by historically justifying that very same bureaucracy, if not
becoming a straightforward apologist for all its crimes.
This is not accidental. Within
the conceptual framework of classical Marxism, classes –
including ruling classes-are at least at some time of their
existence historically inevitable, i.e., necessary instruments
of social organization. If the Soviet bureaucracy is a new
ruling class, and progressive compared to the bourgeoisie, then
the conclusion is unassailable: it has played, at least
temporarily, a necessary and progressive role in Soviet society.
So, after a long detour, one would end where one started.
Granted: the Gulag isn’t so good, the harshest labor code in
the world was rather unpalatable, but was there really any
choice? After all, Russia had to be industrialized and
modernized, and one cannot make an omelet without breaking eggs
– one-could only overcome backwardness by barbaric means.
Yesterday “we” called that building socialism “by barbaric
means.” Today “we” call it building a new class society in
advance of capitalism “by barbaric means.” But today, as
yesterday, “we” have to “objectively” approve of the
bureaucracy – all its despotic crimes notwithstanding – as
“historically necessary.” And so on ad nauseam.
That pitfall is easily avoided
by the Marxist, i.e., Trotskyist, interpretation of Soviet
history and the role of the bureaucracy. Everything which is
progressive about the development of Russia. China, etc., is the
product of a socialist revolution. Everything which is
reactionary is the product of the rule of the bureaucracy. There
is no logical intermeshing but a glaring contradiction between
the two. This implies that the bureaucracy is not a class but a
parasitic cancer on the proletariat’s body: that Soviet
society is not a new despotic mode of production, but a society
in transition between capitalism and socialism, arrested in its
progressive development – bogged down, frozen – by a
bureaucratic dictatorship, which has to be overthrown to reopen
the road toward socialism.
But if the assumption that the
bureaucracy, as a new exploiting ruling class, is a progressive
one compared to the bourgeoisie leads to grave conclusions, the
assumption that it is reactionary compared to the capitalists
has implications ten times worse. It would mean that when
confronted with a conflict between the “new class,” or the
potential “new class,” and the bourgeoisie, one would have
to give critical support to the latter against the former.
IV
If bourgeois society has not
led and does not lead – at least in the foreseeable future –
to proletarian revolutions but to “bureaucratic” ones; if in
a dozen countries not a workers’ state (be it a heavily
bureaucratized one) but a new despotic class society has
replaced capitalism, then, obviously, there was something
basically wrong with the historical projections and perspectives
of Marx and the classical Marxists. Moreover, there was
obviously something basically wrong with their social, economic,
and political analysis of bourgeois society itself, of the
nature of its inner contradictions and especially of the nature
of the modern proletariat.
Marx’s concept of socialism
– which was shared by nearly all socialists until the late
1920s – was that of a free society of associated producers
developed out of the specific economic, social, political,
cultural, and even psychological characteristics of the working
class (the wage-earning class), sketched in the Communist
Manifesto and further refined in the subsequent
writings of Marx and Engels on the subject.
If one believes that capitalism
could lead to a new class society as well as – or, rather,
instead of – socialism, that the working class could itself
throw up such a new “exploiting ruling class” rather than
lead the process of general human emancipation, then the
question arises: Wasn’t that analysis of the revolutionary and
liberating potential of the modern working class completely
wrong from the start? Not a few theoreticians have gone far in
that direction, Baran-Sweezy’s last chapter of Monopoly
Capital being one of the first and most notable efforts along
that road. Recently, the East German oppositional communist
Rudolf Bahro has tarnished his otherwise impressive book The
Alternative – by far the most thorough Marxist
critique which has come out of a country dominated by the
Stalinist bureaucracy since Trotsky’s The Revolution
Betrayed – by an even more outspoken and synthetic
judgment of this kind: “The proletariat struggles
spontaneously only in order to adopt the way of life of the
bourgeoisie, at least of the petty bourgeoisie which is nearest
to it.” Herbert Marcuse, as one could have expected, of course
expresses his enthusiastic agreement with that judgment.
Let us not dwell on the
question whether such a rejection of the classical Marxist
analysis of the working class – the Western one as well as the
Soviet one – does or does not imply that socialism and a
classless society have become impossible. The various attempts
to find a substitute “revolutionary subject” to replace the
modern proletariat – Third World peasants, revolutionary
students, the intelligentsia, or even marginalized paupers –
fail to take into account what was the main advance that Marx
achieved for the socialist movement: that the nature of the
society to be created is at least correlated with the social
nature, the economic power, the socio-political potential, and
the material interests of the “revolutionary subject,” and
not to the degree of moral indignation and individual rebellion
against the existing order of this or that group of people. One
cannot demonstrate how any of the above-mentioned social strata
could develop any of the necessary material and social
conditions for bringing about a truly classless society to a
higher degree than the modern working class. But is it true that
150 years of class struggle of the modern proletariat (leaving
aside the hunger revolts of the earliest stages, which Bahro
correctly exempts from his analysis and characterization) can be
subsumed in the formula of tending “spontaneously ... only to
adopt the bourgeois – or petty bourgeois – way of life”?
How blind one must be to the
rich, manifold, and passionate history of working-class
struggles, where chapters of drab “conformism” stand side by
side with chapters of breath-taking capacity of imagination, of
dating innovation, of unequaled heroism, t o make such an
unwarranted generalization! Were the workers of the Paris
Commune, the revolutionary workers of Russia in 1917-21, of
Germany in 1918-23, of Spain in 1936-37, of Yugoslavia in
1941-45, of Hungary in October-November 1956, of Cuba in
1959-65, of France in May 1968, of Prague in 1968-69, of Italy
in autumn 1969, of Portugal in 1975, of Iran in 1979, just
“spontaneously tending to adopt the life-style of the
bourgeoisie”? And again: Were the workers of Spain in 1975-76
– where for the first time in history we witnessed, in the
face of an intact fascist repressive apparatus, several
political regional general strikes for that typical “bourgeois
life-style demand,” the defense and liberation of political
prisoners – behaving according to Bahro’s precepts? And
these are just the most outstanding examples which come to mind.
One could add dozens of other examples to this list – quite a
few from American working-class history too.
In face of that real picture of
working-class struggle over the last century or so, in face of
the overwhelming historical evidence, the question. “Why
hasn’t there been a victorious socialist revolution in the
West?” has to be reformulated in its historically correct way:
Why has there not yet been such a victory, in spite of the
proletariat’s periodic spontaneous attempts to reconstruct
society along socialist lines – attempts which obviously
confirm the possibility of such victory? Then the answer has to
be looked for in terms of the difficulty of the enterprise, the
role of the subjective factor, the need to have a revolutionary
leadership, the uneven development of proletarian class
consciousness, the role of a deliberate brake played by social
democracy first (Germany 1918-19), the Stalinist parties later
(Spain 1936-37), i.e., the real historical dialectic of the
objective and subjective preconditions for world socialism,
which can only come about as a conscious enterprise by a society
objectively and materially capable of realizing it. There is no
force of this kind in bourgeois society other than the modern
proletariat.
Marxists are not religious
people. Our conviction about the revolutionary potential of the
proletariat is based upon scientific analysis and careful
checking of the historical record – not on irrational faith or
scholastic syllogisms. If overwhelming historical evidence would
show that Marx’s assumptions have been proven wrong, then one
would have no choice but to state the truth – in the true
spirit of Marx himself who, not only as a witticism, stated that
his favorite motto was de omnibus dubitandum.
But we contend that the
evidence provided by history so far does not warrant any such
hasty generalization. It is both Western capitalism and the
dictatorship of the bureaucracy which are in deep and insoluble
social crisis today – not Marxism. If one wants to avoid
retreating into a simple rationalization or one’s own
disappointment with the relative slowness of the historical
process, of one’s revulsion against political misleaders, of
one’s fatigue and demoralization, then one should keep a sense
of proportion and say: let us wait and see how the workers will
fight the next few decades, nay half-century. And let us not
wait passively but do what we can to ensure that these
workers’ struggles end in victorious socialist revolution,
before drawing premature balance-sheets and before barbarism
takes over.
We are back where we started,
but with a vengeance. Yes, the question of whether the Soviet
bureaucracy is a new ruling class is directly linked with the
question of the future of world revolution and, therefore, the
future of humanity. It is likewise directly related to the
question of the revolutionary socialist potential of the working
class, to the very possibility of socialism, i.e., to scientific
socialism as such. For these questions are at the very center of
Marx’s analysis and of the “Marxist system.” And there is
no evidence whatsoever to suggest that this system is no longer
as solid and firmly based as it ever was.
Footnotes
1.
The bureaucracy’s taking of power does not simply “develop
out of the conditions created by the revolution itself” – a
statement which avoids taking a stand on the concrete political
struggles which occurred during the twenties in the USSR! It
develops out of a victorious political counter-revolution (a
“counter-revolution within the revolution,” if one wishes,
the classical precedent being the Thermidor during the French
Revolution). In light of that fact, Sweezy does the Left
Opposition a serious injustice in not mentioning that it started
as early as 1923 – perhaps a couple of years too late, granted
– a consistent struggle for Soviet democracy and increased
political rights for the working class.
|