- Is Ultraleftism Today the “Main Danger” Inside the Fourth International?
- Tail-Ending Reformism
- Tail-Ending Electoralism
- Tail-Ending a New “Stage-Theory” of the Revolution
- Tail-Ending Petty-Bourgeois Nationalism
- Tail-Ending Imperialist Nationalism
- Tail-Ending Elevated to the Level of Principle
13.
Is Ultra-leftism Today the “Main Danger” Inside the Fourth
International?
The rationale of the tendency
struggle which the minority started in the Fourth International
is that the world Trotskyist movement is threatened by the
universal danger of “ultra-leftism.” Starting with the
“guevarist” concept of “rural guerrilla warfare,” the FI
majority is said to be rapidly turning away from orthodox
Trotskyism in one field after another, supporting and extending
“terrorism” into more and more countries, covering up for
the “ultra-left” IMG (British section), turning its back
upon the struggle for democratic demands in more and more
countries, refusing to apply the transitional programme, etc.,
etc. The fact that these accusations are completely unfounded,
does not need to be developed here in detail. “Rural guerrilla
warfare” is neither the line of the 9th World Congress
document, nor has it been applied up to now by any of our
sections (including the Argentine section). Our support for the
transitional programme and “Leninist combat party building”
is a bit firmer, more principled and more applied in practice
than that of some of the most prominent supporters of Comrade
Hansen, as we shall have occasion to prove very soon. But what
about the central thesis of “ultra-leftism” as a universal,
or in any case the “main danger” facing the world Trotskyist
movement?
There is no reason to deny that
a sudden influx of thousands of new members – many of whom are
of student origin – into revolutionary organisations, in a
period of rising and not declining revolutionary tide certainly
carries with it several political dangers, of which a mature
leadership should be conscious and to which it should react in
an appropriate way. Ultra-leftist tendencies are certainly one
of these dangers. Wherever they manifested themselves – e. g.,
in the attitude of some British comrades to the slogan “Vote
Labour” at the 1970 general elections; in the attitude of the
Spanish comrades towards the struggle for democratic demands –
the International leadership has reacted quickly and firmly. We
shall certainly react in the same way in the future, if sections
or groups inside sections want to revise in an ultra-left sense
the programmatic, strategic or tactical legacy of revolutionary
Marxism.
But ultra-leftism is by no
means the only danger for groups which are in the process of
rapid growth – especially not in pre-revolutionary and
revolutionary situations. The large influx of new members into
the Comintern after its first year of existence did not create
exclusively or even mainly ultra-left, but rather opportunist
deviations. There is a general logic about this, which Comrade
Cannon has expressed admirably in his Letters from
Prison:
“There is a somewhat
disturbing consistency in the various issues raised or
adumbrated by the opposition. In addition to the differences
over perspectives, masked as a dispute over democratic
demands, we hear the astonishing contention that the Fourth
International must be on guard against the left danger. If the
perspective is revolutionary, if we are witnessing the
beginning of a great revolutionary upsurge, we must rather
expect manifestations of the right danger in the sharpest
form. That is a historical law.
“Leaving aside individual
aberrations and judging by main currents, we see this law
demonstrated over and over again in every new crisis.
‘Leftism’ is fundamentally a sickness of the labor
movement at ebb tide. It is the produce of revolutionary
impatience, of the impulse to jump over objective
difficulties, to substitute revolutionary zeal and forced
marches for the supporting movement of the masses.
Opportunism, on the other hand, is a disease which strikes the
party in the sharpest form at the moment of social crisis.”
And in an even sharper way,
Comrade Cannon writes:
“In the light of historical
experience, it seems incredible that anyone should see
‘leftism’ as the main danger at the beginning of the
revolutionary crisis. If history teaches us anything, such a
posing of the question must itself be characterized as an
opportunist manifestation.” (James P. Cannon: Letters
from Prison, Merit Publishers, 1968, pp.309-310).
The history of the FI during
the last decade or more bears out this analysis. When the
movement was isolated and stagnating, or growing very slowly,
ultra-left tendencies came to the forefront. Most of the splits
(Healy, Posadas) took place on an ultra-left basis. But as soon
as the climate changed, as the isolation of the movement ended,
the opportunist danger of adapting to the mass movement and
tail-ending it, came to the forefront. Even the ultra-lefts of
yesteryear – like Lambert and Posadas – turned into
right-wing opportunists of the tailist variety. Likewise the big
political betrayals by people claiming to be Trotskyists
occurred in Ceylon (by the reformist LSSP) and in Bolivia by
Lora not in the direction of ultra-leftism, but of right-wing
opportunism and capitulation in the face of reformism and
Stalinism.
The record, therefore, does not
bear out the assessment of Comrade Hansen, of ultra-leftism
being the universal danger menacing the Fourth International
against which a merciless crusade must be organised. And if we
look somewhat closer into the record of several tendencies,
groupings or individuals who appear to be the staunchest
supporters of Comrade Hansen’s crusade, we shall discover that
they are guilty of not a few examples of crass right-wing
opportunism and tail-endism, in direct opposition to some
important principles and traditions of Leninism. And we
shall find that Comrade Hansen, moved by his all-consuming
passion to root out “ultra-leftism” has kept strangely quiet
about these right-wing opportunist deviations, has not raised
them at all in the international debate, has covered up for them
and has entered, for all intents and purposes, into an
unprincipled bloc with those who are guilty of them,
against the “main sinners” who want to transplant “rural
guerrilla warfare” into the factories of Paris, Turin, Liege
or Birmingham.
14.
Tail-Ending Reformism
The position which the LSA/LSO
(Canadian section) leadership – and staunch supporters of the
minority position on Latin America – has adopted towards the
reformist social-democratic party, the NDP in its country, and
its position on the October 30, 1972 general elections in Canada
in particular, expresses a clear tailist deviation from
Leninism. In a leaflet distributed on a large scale before these
general elections, we can find the following gems:
“In order to bring about
positive changes, we need a party that acts in our interests.
The New Democratic Party is the only one that speaks for the
majority – the working class and the other oppressed of
society. It does not get any support from the E.P. Taylors. In
fact, big business hates it. It is financed and supported by
working people. It has been built by working people,
struggling for a better life.
“The NDP is the only
alternative to the status quo in this election. The Lewis
attack on the ‘corporate welfare bums’ shows whose side
the NDP is on. Because it is a party of the working people,
the NDP has been deeply affected by the ongoing struggles of
students, women, antiwar activists and other people fighting
for a change. Its program includes free tuition for students,
US out of Vietnam and an end to Canada’s complicity in the
war, repeal of all anti-abortion laws, free
community-controlled daycare centres.
“The Liberals and Tories
can only block our struggles. The NDP can propel them forward.
An NDP victory would inspire and intensify the different
movements of the oppressed. A Labor government could win
concrete gains for the working people, and open the way for
fundamental social change.
“This is why we’ve got to
campaign for an NDP government and use the 2.8 million new
votes we hold to bring it about.
“The NDP has limitations.
Its conservative leadership wants to reform this profit
system, not end it. The leadership also sees the parliamentary
road as the only way for change, and they sometimes even
oppose demonstrations, mass meetings, strikes, etc.
“But you don’t get
anything ready made. You can either stand on the sidelines and
complain that even our party, the NDP, isn’t what it should
be, or you can join the struggle to make it effective. In
order to change the world, we must organise to see our needs
fulfilled.” (my emphasis – E.G.)
It is true that this
astonishing prose is only published in the name of the Canadian
Young Socialists, and not in the section’s own name. But the
prose of the Canadian section itself is hardly more edifying.
Here is what we can ready in its central organ’s editorial on
the general elections, entitled For the labour Alternative:
Vote NDP Oct. 30!
“The NDP is a class
alternative to the capitalist parties. Its election to power
promises not only many needed reforms for working people and
the poor; not only class legislation aiding the organisation
of the unorganised workers and the bargaining struggles of the
organised; not only legislation repealing discriminatory laws
– but the election of NDP governments to power constitutes
big strides in the path that the working class of this country
are going to take towards breaking not only from
capitalist electoral politics but from capitalism as a system.
“The working class and the
oppressed in Canada, organised politically in a Labour Party
based on the trade union movement is a powerful potential
force against capitalism. Through the NDP, the lessons of the
radi-calisation among youth, in the women’s liberation
movement, the lessons of the Quebec and Native liberation
struggles, are being transmitted to, discussed and debated
among the advanced workers of the country. It is through
the NDP that the political consciousness of the working class
in Canada is being forged and shaped.
“That is what the
profiteers and the bosses of this country fear. And that is
what socialists support. Vote class. Vote NDP on October 30.
Build the NDP.” (Labor Challenge, Sept. 27,
1972 – my emphasis – E.G.)
In a certain sense, the LSA/LSO
appeal is even worse than the YS one. For while it prudently
leaves out the most extreme pro-reformist formulations of the
leaflet, it doesn’t even include the pious reference to the
“conservative leadership” of the NDP and its parliamentary
illusions. In fact, it doesn’t contain a single word of
criticism of reformism and electoralism, not a single word of
differentiation from social-democracy!
We are not dealing here with a
hypothetical Labor Party, arising from a young rebellious and
still partially democratic trade-union upsurge, similar to the
one Trotsky projected in the late Thirties for the USA in
relation to the rise of the CIO. We are talking about a
social-democratic party, with a programme well to the right of
even British social-democracy, not to speak of the French and
Italian socialist parties. We are talking about politicians who
abhor revolution, extra-parliamentary struggles for overthrowing
capitalism, and whose horizon is totally limited to that of
winning reforms within the framework of capitalist economy and
the bourgeois state.
We are talking about people who
are 100% in favor of class-collaboration politically,
economically and socially. In the best of cases, a coming to
power of the NDP would lead to what Trotsky called a miserable
comedy, like the first MacDonald governments in Britain. If
things go worse, it could lead to big defeats and demoralisation
of the working class, if a powerful revolutionary party does not
exist to lead the workers’ struggle beyond social-democratic
reforms and towards socialist revolution.
All this is ABC for any
Leninist, and any supporter of the Fourth International.
Obviously, it is ABC for the leadership of the LSA as well. Why
then do they write the exact opposite of what they believe on
these questions? For “tactical” reasons? Is it part of
Leninist “tactics” to hide the truth from the workers (leave
alone the radicalised vanguard whom you can’t fool for a
minute, and who don’t believe that reformist rubbish anyway)?
Where did Lenin ever advise revolutionary socialists and
communists to call social-democracy an “alternative” to the
bourgeois status quo? Where did he ever say that big business
hates social-democrats (does British capital “hate” Wilson,
not to mention Roy Jenkins)? Did Lenin ever say that a
social-democratic government would open up “the way for
fundamental social change”? What is this strange animal
anyway, supposedly different from a socialist revolution, in the
epoch of imperialism? Did Lenin ever consider that political
class consciousness grows inside the working class through a
strengthening of the reformist mass parties? Isn’t it a
serious deviation for a revolutionary socialist to seriously
write that the election of a reformist government, which will
manage bourgeois society and capitalist relations of production
like all its counterparts have done since 1918, “constitutes
big strides in the path of the working people ... towards
breaking ... from capitalism as a system”? What has any of
this in common with Leninism?
Of course, our criticism does
not imply that it would be incorrect for Canadian revolutionary
Marxists to call upon the workers and other oppressed layers of
society to vote NDP. Lenin taught us to support
social-democratic candidates in elections under certain
conditions “like the rope supports the hanging man.” He
specified that this task poses itself especially when it is a
question of winning a majority of the workers to a communist
party which has already set itself upon the road to such a
conquest. He underlined that before setting upon that
course, it is imperative to assemble, steel and educate the
vanguard. And he specifically lay down the conditions for
denouncing reformism which had to accompany any such
electoral support, lest it lead the masses closer to the
reformist fakers, the labor lieutenants of capital (to whom our
comrades in Canada now refer to, for shame, as “the party of
the working people”!) instead of helping them to free
themselves from reformist illusions and traitors:
“If we are not a
revolutionary group, but the Party of the revolutionary class,
if we want the masses to follow us (and unless they do,
we stand the risk of remaining mere tallers) we must first help
Henderson or Snowden to beat Lloyd George and Churchill (or to
be more correct: to compel the former to beat the latter,
because the former are afraid to win); secondly, help
the majority of the working class to become convinced by their
own experience that we are right, i.e., that the Henderson’s
and Snowden’s are utterly worthless, that they are
petty-bourgeois and treacherous and that their bankruptcy is
inevitable; thirdly, bring nearer the moment when, on the basis
of the disappointment of the majority of the workers in the
Hendersons, it will be possible with serious chances of success
to overthrow the government of the Hendersons at once ...
“... The Communist Party
should propose to the Hendersons and Snowdens that they enter
into a ‘compromise,’ an election agreement, viz., to march
together against the alliance of Lloyd George and the
Conservatives ... while the Communist Party retains complete
liberty to carry on agitation, propaganda and political
activity. Without the latter condition, of course, no such bloc
could be concluded, for that would be an act of betrayal; the
British communists must insist on and secure complete liberty
to expose the Hendersons and the Snowdens in the same way as
(for fifteen years, 1903-1917) the Russian Bolsheviks insisted
on and secured it in relation to the Russian Hendersons and
Snowdens, i.e., the Mensheviks.” (V.I. Lenin, Left-Wing
Communism, An Infantile Disorder, Coop Publishing
Society of Foreign Workers, Moscow 1935, p.84.)
And further:
“If I as a Communist come
out and call upon the workers to vote for the Hendersons
against Lloyd George, they will certainly listen to me. And I
will be able to explain in a popular manner not only why
Soviets are better than parliament and why the dictatorship of
the proletariat is better than the dictatorship of Churchill
(which is concealed behind the signboard of bourgeois
“democracy”), but I will also be able to explain that I
wanted to support Henderson with my vote in the same way as
the rope supports the hanged – that the impending
establishment of a Henderson government will prove I am right,
will bring the masses over to my side, and will accelerate the
political death of the Hendersons and the Snowdens as was the
case with their friends in Russia and Germany.” (Ibid.,
pp.86-87.)
In other words: while Lenin
posed as a condition for a call to vote labour the simultaneous
denunciation of their leaders as worthless, petty-bourgeois and
treacherous, moving towards inevitable bankruptcy; while he
called upon the British Communists to use the hearing they could
get from Labour workers to make communist propaganda in favor of
workers democracy and Soviets, against parliamentary and
reformist illusions, the Canadian section of the Fourth
International, while calling on the workers to vote NDP, abstains
from any such revolutionary propaganda, and indeed
increases the hold of reformism upon the workers by presenting
things as if a “fundamental social change” and “breaking
from capitalism as a system” could be conquered by the masses
through an electoral victory of the NDP. How, under such
circumstances, these same masses could be capable of breaking
with reformism after their experience with the bankruptcy of an
NDP government, and how they could be won over to revolutionary
Marxism remains a mystery.
The trend of the
electoral policies of the LSA/LSO is clear. It can be summarised
in one formula: tail-ending reformism.
15.
Tail-Ending Electoralism
We have already dwelt, in the
first section of this document, on the ways in which the
military dictatorship of General Lanusse decided to switch from
a policy of increased repression to a policy of diverting the
mass movement towards electoral goals, and the way in which it
tried to use the Peronist union and party bureaucracy, as well
as the personality of Juan Peron itself, to eliminate the one
threat which was uppermost in its mind: that the toiling masses
would in increasing numbers take to the streets, that the
general strikes would become semi-insurrectional or even
insurrectional general strikes, and that in this way the
overthrow of capitalism and of the bourgeois state would become
an immediate possibility.
In that precise situation, the
group of Comrade Moreno choose to make participation in the
elections called by the Lanusse regime its main immediate goal
and the main line projected before the mass movement. There is
of course nothing wrong on principle in participating in
bourgeois elections, even under dictatorial regimes, under
rigged election laws and under conditions where real power –
even formal political power – remains firmly in the hands of
the military. After all, the Bolsheviks also participated in
some of the Duma elections under conditions of Tsarist
autocracy. Nor is such participation in itself a matter of
principle either. Whether to participate at all, under which
conditions to participate, is entirely a matter of tactics
depending on the concrete analysis of the concrete situation in
the country, the relationship of forces between the contending
classes, the needs of the mass movement, etc.
But in order to be principled,
participation in such elections must be used as a means of
telling the truth to the toiling masses. Telling the truth does
not mean advancing only some economic demands and making general
propaganda for socialism, but also to denounce the very
existence of the dictatorship and to denounce the fake character
of the “elections” being organised by the military
dictatorship. To remain silent about the existence of the
dictatorship – under the pretext that in this way you
‘gain’ the possibility of legal propaganda – is an
unacceptable concession to electoralism. Marx and Engels
denounced it in German social-democracy, when that party, in
order to comply with reactionary legislation kept quiet about
the undemocratic imperial structure of the German Reich. The
Bolsheviks – in contradiction to the Mensheviks – did not
simply demand a constitution, but when they participated in the
elections for the Fourth (1913) Duma, raised as their first
slogan: “Down with tsarism. Long live the democratic
republic.”
When the Verdad
group absorbed the skeleton “Socialist Party” of Corral,
which was entirely without mass influence or even membership,
with the only purpose to get a legal basis for participation in
the Lanusse elections, it published several platforms both for
its own campaign and its proposals for the mass movement. In none
of these was the fraudulent character of the elections – which
violate on many counts even the official reactionary bourgeois
constitution of Argentina – denounced. This led to the sad
spectacle of Avanzada Socialista interviewing
the trade-union leader Tosco, just released from prison, asking
him what he thought about the idea of a workers slate in the
elections, and receiving the answer from Tosco that first of all
one had to say that these were fraudulent elections. Trotskyists
being taught such an elementary lesson by a CP sympathiser. What
a humiliating experience for comrade Moreno!
The key question on which Avanzada
Socialista has been harping incessantly since the
takeover of the Corral PSA by the Verdad group
(now known as the PST) has been the need for independent working
class candidates in the coming elections. Again, there is
nothing wrong in principle with such a propaganda theme. But
whether it should or should not be the main axis of the
political activity of revolutionary marxists depends entirely on
the objective situation and the dynamics of the class struggle.
The Communist International did not dream of making that the
main issue in Germany or Italy 1919, because the central
question thrown up by the stage reached at that time by the
class struggle in these countries was not independent working
class politics as against workers supporting bourgeois parties,
but it was socialist revolution, i. e., revolutionary as against
reformist policies. One can hardly visualise Trotsky explaining
to the French workers in April 1936 or to the Spanish workers in
January 1936 that the key solution to their problems was the
setting up a “workers and socialist pole” in the coming
elections (which were held under conditions of bourgeois
democracy much freer and more advanced than those of Argentina
today). The task of revolutionary marxists under such conditions
is to increase the distrust of the masses towards bourgeois
elections and bourgeois parliaments, is to explain to them that
their key orientation should be towards extra-parliamentary mass
actions not only for immediate economic demands but also for
solving all their political problems.
In our opinion, the
misjudgement of the objective situation in Argentina and the
dynamics of the class struggle which comrade Moreno’s fraction
and later his independent organisation have been guilty of in
1967-1968 shows itself rather revealingly in the fact that under
the present circumstances – when he himself recognises the
situation as pre-revolutionary – he makes the question of
independent working class candidates in fraudulent elections
under a decaying military dictatorship and not the question of
how to overthrow the dictatorship (how to generalise the
Cordobazos into an Argentinazo), the main axis of his political
activity.
As late as May 18, 1970, La
Verdad wrote commenting on the various concessions made
by the dictatorship to the masses:
“It is certain that with
these measures it tried to isolate and slow down for a few
months the process of mobilisations which had reached an
explosive stage. But as we warned repeatedly in our paper, far
from being in retreat, the working class continued its upsurge
during these months, learning from the experiences of May,
June and September (1969) and started to tackle the two great
tasks which have to be solved so that the next Cordobazo
could become a triumphant insurrection in the whole country:
to win the proletariat of Buenos Aires and the rest of the
country for the mobilisation, and to fundamentally build a
class leadership, to replace the treacherous bureaucrats and
lead the working class and the people in its merciless
struggle against the government and the employers.”
Although the formulations are
incomplete, they give a much more correct orientation than the
turn towards a “workers and socialist pole” in the
elections. How was Argentina ripe for generalised insurrection
in May 1970 and not ripe in the beginning of 1972?
Nevertheless it is a matter of
principle to educate the working class on the necessity of
organising independently from all political parties and machines
of the bourgeois class. Proclaiming that correct principle can
only be welcomed. One therefore would tend to agree with the
draft minority document written by comrades Moreno and Lorenzo
where it states:
“At the same time the
illusions among the masses concerning Peron and Peronism
constitute a standing danger to our own movement, since our
own ranks cannot be sealed off from the milieu in which they
work. This requires absolute clarity on the nature of Peronism
and constant alertness to its invidiousness. “This problem
is well understood by the PRT (La Verdad) in view of
the rich experience in mass work in organisations dominated by
Peronism. The PRT (La Verdad) teaches its members in
the Marxist tradition of insisting on the independence of the
working class movement against any and all blocs with the
national bourgeoisie. Precisely because of the opening which
has been developing on the electoral front, the PRT
(Verdad) has been stressing its opposition to any
populist, nationalist or popular-front formation that seeks to
induce the workers into turning away from independent action
and voting for bourgeois candidates as in the case of the
Frente Ampilio in Uruguay or the Unidad Popular in Chile.” (International
Internal Discussion Bulletin, Jan. ’73, pp.38-39)
But hardly had the ink dried on
the mimeographed copies of comrades Moreno and Lorenzo’s draft
presented to the December 1972 IEC, when briefly, Peron,
returned to Argentina and was greeted by a big wave of mass
enthusiasm as could easily have been foreseen. The Verdad
group immediately bowed under Peronist mass pressure, contrary
to all its lofty and principled proclamations. The November
15th, 1972 issue of Avanzada Socialista
appeared with a headline covering the whole first page:
“GENERAL PERON: Let Him Propose a Plan of Struggle and 80%
(sic) workers’ Candidates.” The main article in the paper,
under this headline, ended as follows:
“There are peronist
comrades who, while accepting this danger [that Peron aligns
himself with the right-wing bureaucracy of the CGT under Ricci
– E.G.] say that Peron has been forced into that
position, he has been encircled by trade union bureaucrats and
by Campora and Osindi. We believe that unfortunately that is
not true, and that fundamentally Peron defends the employers
and accepts the agreement consciously. But even if these
comrades were right and we were wrong, the way out for the
labour movement can only be the following one.
“Let us demand from Peron a
plan of struggle for a wage increase of 50.000$ and a minimum
wage of 120.000, readapted every two months, and against
unemployment!
“Let us ask him that he
keeps open 80% of the candidates of the Partido Justicialista
[Peron’s party – E.G.] so that the workers can
themselves elect their candidates!
“If the fault doesn’t lie
with Peron, we shall thereby help him to break the
encirclement by the bureaucrats. If unfortunately things are
like we believe them to be, the workers themselves should
impose the plan of struggle and the workers candidates.”
So it was sufficient only for
Peron to make a brief trip to Argentina for all the big pledges
in favour of working class independence to be forgotten and for
the presentation of 80% workers candidates by the bourgeois
Justicialista Party, which stands for class collaboration and
class peace, and never had any Marxist, socialist, not to say
revolutionary, communist plank in its programme, to be presented
as the “only way for the Argentine labour movement.” The
logic of tail-ending, and of tail-ending electorism, is harsh
indeed!
This is no isolated accident in
the history of the Moreno group. There is another example of
Comrade Moreno dabbling in electoral popular fronts: the case of
the Uruguayan grouping (PRT–U) participating in the ill-famed
Frente Amplio during the 1971 general elections. The minority
draft presented to the December 1972 IEC publishes a couple of
embarrassed paragraphs on this subject, which can only be called
distorting facts by omission.
While the authors of that draft
correctly remind us that comrade Hansen wrote – a rather mild
– criticism of that opportunist manoeuvre, they fail to
mention:
- that the United Secretariat
of the Fourth International condemned outright this form of
class collaboration, which implied calling upon the Uruguyan
workers to elect bourgeois general Serengi as President of
the Republic.
- that the PRTU is led by a
member of the central committee of the Verdad grouping – a
“cadre of long standing” of the organisation led by
comrade Moreno as was stated by the latter at the December
1972 IEC.
- That La Verdad
had publicly supported that opportunist maneuver before,
during and after the event and, to our knowledge never
corrected that mistake in public.
- that the chief justification
for the participation of a group claiming to be Trotskyist
in a popular front with one of the main bourgeois groupings
of Uruguay was the excuse that without supporting the Frente
Amplio slate it would have been “technically impossible”
to present “Trotskyist candidates” in the elections.
This is, once again, a typical case of tail-ending
electorism, where the participation in the elections becomes
a goal in itself, blown up to the point where it takes
precedence over matters of programmatic principles. In fact
this very same argument of electoralist expediency was used
by the POUM in 1936 to justify its participation in the
Spanish Popular Front – we all know with what disastrous
effects.
16.
Tail-Ending a New “Stage-Theory” of the Revolution
The tendency towards
opportunist tail-ending has manifested itself in the Canadian
section not only through its attitude towards social-democracy
but also via its attitude towards the national question in its
own country. In the September/October 1972 issue of Liberation,
the organ of the LSO, we find the following statements signed by
Comrade Alain Beiner, in relation to a recent split which
occurred within the LSO:
“Au contraire des positions
de Lénine et Trotsky sur la lutte nationale d’un peuple
opprimé, la tendance refusait de soutenir inconditionellement
le nationalisme québécois. La tendance n’acceptait pas la
théorie de la Révolution permanente formulée par Trotsky et
confirmée par la Révolution russe; selon laquelle la
bourgeoisie nationale d’une nation opprimée (comme le Québec)
est incapable a cause de sa dépendance de 1’impérialisme
mondial, de rompre tout lien avec lui pour diriger une lutte
de libération nationale a bonne fin centre 1’oppression étrangère.
Pour la tendance les ‘dangers’ d’une ‘récupération
facile’ du nationalisme et des luttes nationales au Québec
par la bourgeoisie et ses partis (comme le PQ) primaient sur
la portée tout à fait révolutionnaire de la lutte d’émancipation
nationale.” [1]
We shall deal furthermore with
the completely non-Leninist identification of “national
liberation” or “the right of self-determination of
nations” on the one hand, and “nationalism” on the other
hand. Let us first of all clarify what is programmatically wrong
in Comrade Beiner’s summary of what he thinks to be
Trotsky’s theory of the permanent revolution, and what is in
reality a revision of that very same theory.
Is it true that, because the
national bourgeoisie is dependent upon imperialism, it is unable
to break all ties with imperialism and therefore cannot
lead a victorious struggle against foreign oppression?
This is completely wrong. The struggle against national
oppression is not an anti-capitalist struggle. It is a struggle
for a bourgeois-democratic demand. The existence of the world
capitalist system is not an absolute obstacle to the overthrow
of national oppression, under conditions of imperialism. Indeed,
in the very debate with Rosa Luxemburg in favour of the support
for the right of self-determination of oppressed nationalities,
Lenin pointed out that it was not impossible for this
right to be gained in the struggle, before the overthrow of
world imperialism. In fact, from the case of Norway cited by
Lenin, to that of Poland and Finland who conquered their
national independence in 1918, to that of most of the former
colonial countries of Asia and Africa who conquered independence
after 1947, the history of the 20th century has confirmed that
it is not necessary to “break all ties with imperialism” in
order to eliminate foreign national oppression.
Of course, under imperialism
– especially in its epoch of decay – the struggle against
national oppression becomes more and more difficult on a global
scale. New forms of national oppression arise constantly, even
when old ones are partially eliminated. Where foreign national
oppression is eliminated, foreign economic exploitation
remains and increases. The inability of the national bourgeoisie
to start a process of cumulative industrialisation makes it in
many cases impossible to create a national market and thereby to
bring to an end the process of formation of a classical nation
in the historic sense of the word. But all this raises questions
which are far beyond the realm of “foreign national
oppression.” To say that India, Indonesia or Nigeria, not to
speak about Brazil, Argentina, Finland or Turkey, are today
countries in which foreign national oppression by
imperialism reigns would be obviously misleading.
Trotsky never stated that in
the epoch of imperialism, the “national” bourgeoisie in a
backward country is unable to begin waging a struggle
for some of the historical demands of the bourgeois
democratic revolution. On the contrary, he stressed time and
time again that the beginning of such a struggle under bourgeois
or petty-bourgeois leadership was nearly inevitable. Such was
the case not only in Poland and Finland, but in nearly all the
colonial countries of Asia and Africa. Where he opposed himself
sharply to “marxist orthodoxy” as it had been represented up
to 1906 by the whole of international social-democracy was in
his understanding that it was basically wrong to separate
different revolutionary tasks as if they presented themselves in
different successive stages of mass struggle. The theory of the
permanent revolution was born from the discovery of the law of
uneven and combined development, i.e., of the combination of
tasks with which the masses in a backward country are
simultaneously faced under conditions of imperialism.
The discovery of this law of
uneven and combined development results from an analysis of the
sum total of social and economic relations which prevail in
these countries in the 20th century. The national bourgeoisie is
not only tied to imperialism but also to the
landlord-moneylender-compradore class. The national question is
not the only key question of the bourgeois democratic revolution
which remains unfulfilled in backward countries in the 20th
century. Apart from the question of democratic political rights
of the toiling masses and of initiating a process of cumulative
industrialisation, there is the decisive question of the
agrarian revolution. But when the peasant masses rise to
overthrow the landlords-usurer-merchant alliance, they not only
often attack direct property (capital investments) of the
“national bourgeoisie” too, but they also create in the
country a revolutionary situation which challenges the rule of
propertied classes in general, thereby assisting the challenge
of the proletariat against the private property of the national
bourgeoisie itself.
All these reasons have to be
added to the “national” bourgeoisie’s links with
imperialism in order to understand why, while it can certainly start
the struggle for some demands of the
bourgeois-democratic revolution, it cannot fulfil them all,
especially not the agrarian revolution and the break with the
capitalist world market as a necessary precondition for a
cumulative industrialisation process. More: because it fears
mass uprisings of peasants and workers, and because the process
of revolution, even when it starts around the demand of national
independence, inevitably will bring large masses of peasants and
workers to struggle for their own immediate and historic class
demands, the “national” bourgeoisie will inevitably go over
to the camp of the counter-revolution at some stage of the
struggle. Therefore the choice before the revolution in a
backward country is either the victory of counter-revolution, if
the “national” bourgeoisie remains in the leadership – and
in that case essential parts of the historic tasks of the
bourgeois democratic revolution remain unfulfilled – or the
conquest of hegemony in the revolutionary struggle (i.e., over
rural and urban petty-bourgeois masses) by the proletariat and
its independent revolutionary party. In that case the revolution
can triumph. Through the establishment of the dictatorship of
the proletariat allied to the poor peasantry it will combine the
thorough realisation of the tasks of the bourgeois-democratic
revolution with the fulfillment of the essential tasks of the
proletarian socialist revolution.
This whole analysis of concrete
social forces and their mutual inter-relations hinges precisely
upon the refusal to separate any stage of “national
liberation” from a subsequent “stage” of agrarian
revolution, and a still later stage of “independent working
class struggle.” The whole essence of the theory of permanent
revolution derives from the understanding that all these tasks
are combined and intertwined from the beginning of the
revolutionary process, as the result of the class reality and
the class relations prevailing in these countries.
It was the Comintern leadership
under Stalin-Bucharin which formulated the theory of a “first
stage of national liberation struggle,” hi which the
“main” enemy was supposedly foreign imperialism, and in
which for that reason the struggles of the workers
against capitalist property, and the struggle of the peasants
against the class alliance of their exploiters, had to be
subordinated to the “common and most pressing goal” of
conquering national independence. Revolutionary marxists do not
reject this Menshevik theory of stages only or mainly because
they stress the inability of the national bourgeoisie to
actually conquer national independence from imperialism,
regardless of concrete circumstances. They reject it because
they refuse to postpone to a later stage the peasant and workers
uprisings for their own class interests, which will inevitably
rise spontaneously alongside the national struggle as it
unfolds, and very quickly combine themselves into a common
inseparable programme in the consciousness of the masses.
It has become the Stalinist
line towards the colonial revolution that there has been after
1945 a “stage of national liberation struggles,” which is
supposed to solve the problems of the bourgeois-democratic
revolution, as it remains common Stalinist theory that the
“bourgeois-democratic revolution” was fulfilled in Russia in
February 1917, thereby opening the stage for the “socialist
October revolution.” Trotsky and Trotskyists categorically
reject this theory of “stages.” The tasks of the
bourgeois-democratic revolution cannot be reduced to national
independence or the suppression of foreign national oppression,
any more than they can themselves be separated into successive
stages. It is because the agrarian question was not solved by
the February revolution, in spite of the overthrow of the tsar,
that the October revolution was objectively possible, i.e., that
the proletariat was not isolated from the great majority of the
peasantry. It is because the agrarian question is not solved
today in any of the semi-colonial countries which conquered
national independence after World War 2 that in spite of the
minority situation of the proletariat, the establishment of the
dictatorship of the proletariat allied to the poor peasantry
remains a realistic perspective.
For that reason, it is
confusing, to say the least, to present any revolution in a
backward country – be it the Algerian revolution, the Cuban
revolution, the Vietnamese revolution, the Palestinian or the
Arab revolution – as a “national liberation struggle.” The
Trotskyist way of looking at these revolutions is as processes
of permanent revolution in which the struggle for national
liberation, for agrarian revolution, for full democratic
freedoms for the masses, and for defence of the class interests
of the working class are inextricably combined and
intertwined, whatever may be the aspect of that struggle
which appears in the forefront (and very often appearance and
reality are at variance with each other. In South Vietnam, to
take that most telling example, the liberation struggle of the
peasantry against their exploiters has probably mobilised more
people and covered more ground since the early fifties than the
struggle against foreign counter-revolutionary imperialist
intervention).
If we reject any theory of
stages even ini backward colonial and semi-colonial countries,
we have to reject them all the more in advanced imperialist
countries, in which unsolved problems of national oppression
survive or newly arise. As Trotsky pointed out in The
Transitional Programme, even in fascist countries, a
revolutionary programme should base itself on the dialectics
of the class struggle, and not on episodic aspects of the
political superstructure:
“Of course, this does not
mean that the Fourth International rejects democratic slogans
as a means of mobilising masses against fascism. On the
contrary, such slogans at certain moments can play a serious
role. But the formulas of democracy (freedom of press, the
right to unionise, etc.) mean for us only incidental or
episodic slogans in the independent movement of the
proletariat and not a democratic noose fastened to the
neck of the proletariat by the bourgeoisie’s agents
(Spain!). As soon as the movement assumes something of a mass
character, the democratic slogans will be intertwined with the
transitional ones; factory committees, it may be supposed,
will appear before the old routinists rush from their
chancelleries to organise trade unions ...” (p.44 of the
1939 edition by the SWP) (our stress)
Neither in imperialist
countries with a fascist regime, nor in imperialist countries
which, under conditions of decaying bourgeois democracy witness
phenomena of oppressed national minorities within their
boundaries, can there be any “stage” of “democratic
revolution,” of “national liberation,” separate and apart
from the general upsurge of the proletariat which represents the
majority of the population of these countries. The “formulas
of democracy” (and national liberation is a formula
of democracy) becomes intertwined with proletarian, objectively
socialist goals, as soon as the movement assumes a mass
character. The experience of Quebec admirably bears out
this prediction of Trotsky’s: As soon as a significant
(although still minority) sector of the Quebecois working class
was drawn into large mass actions, the nature of the mass
movement took on more and more clearly defined proletarian,
i.e., objectively revolutionary socialist aspects.
The public service employees
organised a general strike in May 1972. Examples of workers
control – probably the most advanced ever seen in North
America – arose. Radio stations were seized and occupied by
the workers and transformed into weapons of strike propaganda.
Even a whole town was seized by the strikers for more than 48
hours. Yet prisoners of their backsliding into a new version of
a theory of stages, the editors of the July/August 1972 issue of
Liberation blandly present in a huge headline
this issue general strike as an example of “the struggle of
the Quebecois for national liberation” on the same level and
in the same spirit as the “patriots rebellion” of ... 1837!
There is no justification for
comrade Mill’s group’s split from the LSA-LSO. In our view,
comrades who have serious differences with the majority line of
their national sections should fight for their political views
inside these sections.
But this being said,
objectivity demands to state unequivocally that Comrade Mill has
been proved right against the majority leadership of the
Canadian section in both instances where he differed with it on
the national question. He requested the section to take up the
demand for an independent Quebec several years before the
leadership came around to that position. Thereafter he requested
the leadership to acknowledge the dynamics of the class struggle
in Quebec, which he understood correctly to be the most advanced
in North America, and to combine more and more in its propaganda
and its agitation socialist with national demands. In the first
instance, the leadership of the section stubbornly refused to
raise the independence slogan till the very eve of the outbreak
of an independentist mass movement. In the second instance, the
leadership of the section stubbornly clung to the concentration
on the language slogans in spite of a general strike of 200,000
workers with the appearance of workers control.
In both cases the roots of the
mistake are evident: tail-endism. The majority leadership of the
LSA-LSO waited till the masses had already clearly shown a given
“mood” before they were ready to adapt their slogans to that
mood. This is, to say the least, a bizarre application of the
concept of a “Leninist vanguard party.” Should the
main distinctive quality of communists inside the mass movement
not be the one to understand and spell out the direction in
which the movement has to develop because of its objective
logic, and the historical class interests which it represents,
rather than to wait until the masses spontaneously discover this
logic and start to act upon it, before daring to unfold it
before their eyes?
In its so-called Action
Programme, of July 1972, which the LSO leadership never
officially repudiated, the reversal to a new edition of the
Menshevik “theory of stages” of the Quebecois revolution is
pushed to its logical extreme. The programme culminates in the
demand for a “democratic republic,” complete with blueprint
how to organise bourgeois democracy (with a president of the
Republic, a National Assembly and the like) in Quebec.
And this under circumstances
where, as that same LSO leadership admits, “since 1970, the
fiercest attacks on the Quebec working class’s standard of
living and rights have been made by the Quebec bourgeoisie and
the Quebec government” (Draft Quebec resolution
submitted to the Political Committee of the LSA-LSO, Discussion
Bulletin of the LSA-LSO, December 1972, p.6).
Presumably, what the Quebecois
Trotskyists should concentrate their fire on, is not this fierce
attack of the Quebec bourgeois against the workers’ interests,
but the “inability” of those “national traitors,” the
bourgeoisie, to cut themselves loose from imperialism in order
to create an independent bourgeois state of French Quebec. That
is the logic of tail-ending a new “stage-theory” of the
revolution.
17.
Tail-Ending Petty-Bourgeois Nationalism
There is another aspect to the
LSA-LSO error on the national question which expresses itself in
Comrade Beiner’s article quoted above. This is the
identification of the right of national self-determination, and
the mass struggles evolving around that right, i.e., concrete
demands and slogans which express it, with “nationalism.”
This identification leads Comrade Beiner to the preposterous
statement that the “positions of Lenin and Trotsky” imply
“unconditional support for Quebecois nationalism” (or for
nationalism of any oppressed nation). This is absolutely untrue.
Both Lenin and Trotsky, in all
their basic writings on the national question, draw a clear
distinction between the need for Marxists to defend the right of
self-determination of nations which do not wish to remain within
a given bourgeois state boundary – otherwise, Marxists become
objectively accomplices to annexionism – and the principled
opposition which they have to maintain to bourgeois or
petty-bourgeois nationalism. Nationalism is an ideology, the
ideology of national solidarity irrespective of regional, ethnic
or social differences. This ideology played a progressive role
essentially in the 16th, 17th and 18th century, i.e., in the
classical period of bourgeois-democratic revolution of the
pre-industrial era, when the bourgeoisie was historically a
revolutionary class. It was a powerful ideological and political
weapon against two reactionary social forces: particularistic
feudal or semi-feudal regional forces, which resisted their
integration into modern nations; native or foreign absolute
monarchs and their aids and props, which resisted that emergence
even more desperately. With the development of capitalist
industry in the 19th century, nationalism gradually loses its
progressive character. The triumphant bourgeoisie uses that
ideology now less against – rapidly disappearing –
pre-capitalist reactionary social forces, and more and more
against its foreign capitalist competitors (or worse: other
nations whose territory it wants oppressively to include in its
own “home market”) and against the working class.
“National solidarity” is called upon to stifle the rise of
the proletarian class struggle.
With the epoch of imperialism,
nationalism as a rule becomes reactionary, whether it
is “purely” bourgeois or petty-bourgeois in character. The
universal idea of independent organisation of the
working class, of the autonomous class goals followed by the
proletariat and the poor peasantry in the class struggle, of international
class solidarity of the workers of all countries and all
nationalities, is opposed to the idea of national solidarity or
national community of interests. In the best of cases – when
advanced among oppressed nations – it is a narrow, parochial
substitute and cover for the programme of the permanent
revolution, i.e., national and social emancipation. In most
cases – when advocated by the capitalist class or its
ideological representatives – it is a thoroughly deceptive and
mystifying ideology to prevent or retard independent class
organisation and class struggle by the workers and poor
peasants.
Sectarians and opportunists
alike fail to make this basic distinction between the struggle
for national self-determination and nationalist ideology.
Sectarians refuse to support national self-determination
struggles under the pretext that their leaders – or the still
prevalent ideology among their fighters – is nationalism.
Opportunists refuse to combat bourgeois or petty-bourgeois
nationalist ideologies, under the pretext that the national-self
determination struggle, in which this ideology is predominant,
is progressive. The correct Marxist-Leninist position is to
combine full support for the national self-determination
struggle of the masses including all the concrete demands which
express this right on the political, cultural, linguistic field,
with the struggle against bourgeois and petty-bourgeois
nationalism.
This principled opposition to
nationalism does not imply an identification between nationalism
of oppressor nations – nationalism of scoundrels, as Trotsky
used to call it – and the nationalism of oppressed nations. It
especially imposes on communists who are members of oppressor
nations the duty to concentrate their fire upon their own
oppressive bourgeoisie, and to leave the struggle against
petty-bourgeois nationalism of the oppressed to the communist
members of the oppressed nationalities themselves. Any other
attitude – not to speak of the refusal to support national
self-determination struggles under the pretext that they are
still lead by nationalists – becomes objectively a support for
imperialist, annexionist or racialist oppressors. But all these
considerations do not imply a support for bourgeois or
petty-bourgeois nationalism by revolutionary Marxists of the
oppressed nationalities, leave alone “unconditional
support.” After all, Alain Beiner like Michel Mill were
discussing the attitudes of Quebecois Trotskyists, not
the attitude of Anglo-Canadian revolutionary Marxists.
Lenin’s position on this
question is unequivocal. In his major contribution to the
national question, his 1914 article The Right of
Self-Determination of Nations, Lenin makes crystal clear
that “workers are hostile to all nationalism” (p.434). He
says that it is impossible to march towards our class goal,
socialism, without “fighting against all and every
nationalism” (p.436). He stresses that to struggle against
capitalist exploitation, the proletariat must be alien towards
all forms of nationalism, included that of oppressed nations
(p.448). He concludes his article by saying that the proletariat
has the dual task of struggling for national self-determination
and of combating all nationalism (p.480). It is often overlooked
that, while chiding Rosa Luxemburg for not accepting that the
Russian Marxists should proclaim and support the right of
self-determination of Polish, Finnish, Georgian, and other
nationalities oppressed by tsarism, he lauds her for struggling,
as a Polish Marxist, against Polish nationalism (pp.454, 458.)
All references are to the French edition of Lenin’s Works,
Vol.20, Editions Sociales, Paris 1959).
In his next major article
devoted to that same question, written in the midst of the first
imperialist war (Results of the discussion on the right of
self-determination, October 1916), Lenin fully maintains
the same position. And in his final major contribution to the
question, which has programmatic value, his Thesis on the
National and Colonial Question, written for the 2nd
Congress of the Comintern, we read the following illuminating
passage:
“Le Parti communiste,
interprète conscient du prolétariat en lutte centre le joug
de la bourgeoisie, doit considérer comme formant la clef de
voûte de la question nationale, non des principes abstraits
et formels, mais: 1) une notion claire des circonstances
historiques et économiques; 2) la dissociation précise des
intérêts des classes opprimées, des travailleurs, des
exploités, par rapport a la conception générale des
soi-disant intérêts nationaux, qui signifient en réalité
ceux des classes dominantes; 3) la division tout aussi nette
et précise des nations opprimées, dépendantes, protégées
– et oppressives et exploiteuses, jouissant de tous les
droits, contrairement a 1’hypocrisie bourgeoise et
démocratique qui dissimule, avec soin, 1’asservissement
(propre à l’époque du capital financier de
l’impérialisme) par la puissance financière et
colonisatrice, de l’immense majorité des populations du
globe à une minorité de riches pays capitalistes.”
“C’est la pratique
habituelle non seulement des partis du centre de la II
Internationale, mais aussi de ceux qui ont abandonné cette
Internationale pour reconnaître l’internationalisme en
paroles et pour lui substituer en realité dans la propagande,
l’agitation et la pratique, le nationalisme et le pacifisme
des petits-bourgeois. Cela se voit aussi parmi les partis qui
s’intitulent maintenant communistes ... Le nationalisme
petit-bourgeois restreint l’internationalisme à la
reconnaissance du principe d’égalité de nations et (sans
insister davantage sur son caractère purement verbal)
conserve intact l’égoïsme national ...”
“Il existe dans les pays
opprimés deux mouvements qui, chaque jour, se séparent de
plus en plus: le premier est le mouvement bourgeois
démocratique nationaliste qui a un programme
d’indépendance politique et d’ordre bourgeois; l’autre
est celui des paysans et des ouvriers ignorants et pauvres
pour leur émancipation de tout espèce d’exploitation.
“Le premier tente de
diriger le second et y a souvent reussi dans une certaine
mesure. Mais l’Internationale communiste et les partis
adhérents doivent combattre cette tendance et chercher à
développer les sentiments de classe indépendants dans les
masses ouvrières des colonies.” (Manifestes,
Thèses et Résolutions des quatre premiers congrès de
l’Internationale communiste, Librairie du Travail,
Paris 1934, pp.57, 58, 60.) [2]
Trotsky, like Lenin,
counterposes support to national self-determination demands to
the duty to fight against nationalism (e.g. History of
the Russian Revolution, vol.2, p.357 of the German
edition). In his writings on the Spanish revolution, several
times we find that while stressing the need for Spanish Marxists
to support the right of the Basque and Catalan nationalities for
self-determination, there are at the same time severe attacks
against the right-wing “Catalan Federation” of the CP, which
later, after its break with Stalinism, renamed itself the
“Workers and Peasant Bloc” and finally fused with the
majority of the Spanish Left Oppositionists to become the main
force of the POUM, which was born from this fusion. Trotsky
heaped scorn upon the “Catalan nationalism” of these
right-wing opportunists.
The materialist basis of this
struggle against contemporary nationalism is admirably clarified
by Trotsky in the following passage:
“The task of complete
national determination and peaceful cooperation of all peoples
of Europe can be solved only on the basis of the economic
unification of Europe, purged of bourgeois rule ...
“It must be clearly
understood beforehand that the belated revolutions in Asia and
Africa are incapable of opening up a new epoch of renaissance
for the national state. The liberation of the colonies will be
merely a gigantic episode in the world socialist revolution,
just as the belated democratic overturn in Russia which was
also a semicolonial country, was only the introducation to the
socialist revolution” (War and the Fourth International,
Writings of Leon Trotsky 1933-34, pp.305,
306).
This Leninist opposition to
nationalism is not an abstract and formal principle, but starts,
as Lenin indicates, from a “clear notion of the historical and
economic circumstances.” That is why there can be some
exceptions to the rule based upon exceptional “historical and
economic circumstances,” i.e. those of oppressed nationalities
which do not yet possess their own ruling class, or which have
only such a miserable embryo of a bourgeois that, in the given
and foreseeable situation, it is excluded that this embryo could
actually become a ruling class without a complete disintegration
of the imperialist structure. The best example of such
exceptions are of the black and Chicano nationalities inside the
United States. We shall discuss them in more detail in the final
section of this text.
But it is clear that neither
Quebec, Catalonia, the Basque country, India, Ceylon nor the
Arab nation, can be classified as exceptional. All these nations
have their own bourgeois class. Many of them even have their own
semi-colonial bourgeois state. To support nationalism within
these nationalities, under the pretext of supporting
anti-imperialist liberation struggles, or even to defend the
doctrine that “consistent nationalism” would automatically
lead to a struggle for the dictatorship of the proletariat, is
to lose the “clear notion of the historical and economic
circumstances,” to lose sight of the class structure, the
class decisions and the irreconcilable class conflicts inside
these nations, which national oppression or economic
exploitation by imperialism in no way eliminates but, in a
certain sense, even exacerbates when compared to what occurs in
non-oppressed nations. To defend the notion of “unconditional
support” for Quebecois nationalism, Arab nationalism, Indian
nationalism, or Ceylon nationalism, is to disarm the workers and
poor peasants of these countries in their class struggle against
their own bourgeoisie, is to make the conquest of power by the
proletariat in the course of the anti-imperialist struggle –
i.e. the whole process of permanent revolution – more
difficult if not impossible, and puts a big obstacle on the road
of building Leninist parties among these nationalities.
An analysis of the concrete
historical and economic circumstances in which national
oppression presents itself is a vital starting point for
adopting a correct position towards the national question. In
that sense it is inadmissable to identify national oppression
inside imperialist countries with national oppression inside
colonial countries. The whole notion of applying the formula of
permanent revolution to imperialist countries is extremely
dubious in the best of cases. It can only be done with the
utmost circumspection, and in the form of an analogy.
Not a single
bourgeois-democratic revolution in the past has solved all its
historical tasks. The survival of bourgeois society under
conditions of the growing decay of capitalism has wholly or
partially destroyed some of the conquests of past victorious
bourgeois revolutions as well. Under these circumstances, there
is undoubtedly an element of combined historical tasks with
which the proletarian revolution will be faced in every country.
The very fact that all revolutionary Marxist organisations in
all countries have to struggle in different proportions for
certain democratic demands bears testimony to that combined
character of all contemporary revolutions.
But it would be pure sophistry
to draw the conclusion that no qualitative difference exists
between the combined tasks facing the revolution in
imperialists, and those facing it in colonial or semi-colonial
countries, simply because of the undeniable fact that some tasks
of the bourgeois-democratic revolution remain unsolved in the
most advanced imperialist nations, or rise up again there,
whereas all the basic tasks of that revolution remain unsolved
(or solved only in a miserably uncomplete way) in the colonial
and semi-colonial countries. Trotsky pointed out in the Transitional
Programme that
“the relative weight of the
individual democratic and transitional demands in the
proletariat’s struggle, their mutual ties and their order of
presentation, is determined by the pecularities and specific
conditions of each backward country and to a considerable
extent – by the degree of its backwardness.” (ibidem,
p.41).
This concept is already
sufficient to indicate how inadmissable it is to ascribe to the
national self-determination struggle of the Quebecois or of the
Basque nationality a similar weight in the Canadian revolution
or in the revolution on the Iberian peninsula as, say, the
national self-determination struggle of the black people in the
revolution in Southern Africa.
Both the objective and the
strategic aspects of this difference need clarification. Trotsky
clarified the objective significance of the struggle for
national independence in colonial and semi-colonial countries in
the following way:
“Japan and China are not on
the same historical plane. The victory of Japan will signify
the enslavement of China, the end of her economic and social
development, and the terrible strengthening of Japanese
imperialism. The victory of China will signify, on the
contrary, the social revolution in Japan and the free
development, that is to say unhindered by external oppression,
of the class struggle in China” (Writings of Leon
Trotsky 1937-38, p. 108).
Inside imperialist nations,
national oppression does not have the same function. The
oppressed Polish and Finnish nationalities, far from being on a
lower historical plane than Tsarist Russia, were in fact
economically and socially richer and industrially more developed
than the oppressor nationality. In no way can one say that
national oppression meant for them “enslavement” and “the
end of economic and social development.” The same applies for
the Basque and Catalan nationalities inside Spain, before 1936
and partially even today. National oppression has not stopped or
thwarted capitalist development or industrialisation in these
oppressed nationalities.
Strategically, the implications
are even more far-reaching. In semi-colonial and colonial
countries, democratic demands have generally the weight of
transitional demands. It is impossible to realise them under
capitalism, at least in their collective essence. In imperialist
countries, this is not true. Democratic demands will normally
not be granted by the decaying imperialist bourgeoisie. But
nothing organically, economically, socially, (i.e. in terms of
basic class relations), prevents the bourgeoisie from granting
them as a “lesser evil” in order to avoid a mass movement
approaching a victorious socialist revolution. Organically, the
“national bourgeoisie” of the colonial world cannot solve
the agrarian question without to a large extent expropriating
itself. There is no fundamental obstacle of the same kind to
prevent the realisation of free abortion on demand, or freedom
of the press, or even a democratic electoral law in an
imperialist country. Given a powerful mass upsurge with a
revolutionary potential, the imperial bourgeoisie can grant
these concessions precisely in order to avoid expropriation.
In normal circumstances,
imperialism was in the past never willing to grant national
independence to Poland or Finland; nor is it prepared to do so
even today to Quebec or Ireland. But given a pre-revolutionary
situation, a powerful upsurge of the workers’ struggle, a
concrete danger of a “workers’ republic” being set up,
there is no fundamental class interest which would prevent
imperialism from transforming any such nationality into
independent puppet states.
For these reasons the danger of
a mass struggle in an imperialist country based solely on
demands for national self-determination being absorbed by the
bourgeoisie is very real. That is why revolutionary marxists
must constantly combine in their propaganda and agitation,
demands expressing the right of national self-determination for
oppressed minorities with demands of a proletarian and socialist
character in order to make this absorption much more difficult.
To relate the proletarian demands to a ‘later stage,’
presumably when the mass movement is “more advanced,” is to
objectively increase the danger of diversion. This is what
Trotsky meant when he argued that we must prevent democratic
demands in imperialist countries from becoming “a democratic
noose fastened to the neck of the proletariat.”
18.
Tail-Ending Imperialist Nationalism
During the summer of 1972, we
were confronted with an extraordinary spectacle. Within the
space of a month, the Central Committee of the Canadian section,
the LSA/LSO, first nearly unanimously adopted the general line
of a political resolution expressing support for “Canadian
nationalism” as against “US domination of Canada,” and
then rejected the very same line by an overwhelming majority.
We don’t want to concentrate
on the somewhat disturbing formal aspects of this development.
How is it possible that without a word of explanation a majority
of Trtoskyist leaders can adopt two completely conflicting
positions, within a few weeks of each other, one of which is
totally alien to the tradition of Leninism? Canada is an
imperialist country. The fact that there is a strong economic
weight of foreign imperialists inside Canada does not modify in
the least this basic character of Cana-cian society. Nationalism
in imperialist nations is essentially a weapon of
inter-imperialist competition (and secondarily a weapon of
annexionism). Foreign imperialist influence in Tsarist Russia
was as big as it is in Canada today. Can one imagine Lenin under
any circumstances supporting Great-Russian nationalism in
Tsarist Russia because of that economic situation, e.g.
Great-Russian nationalism against “foreign domination” by
French, British, German, finance capital?
How could an experienced
Trotskyist leader like Comrade Ross Dowson, trained for decades
in the Trotskyist programme, arrive at such a gravely wrong
position? Why did the large bulk of the Central Committee of the
Canadian section follow him at first on that line? Because the
method of approach to the national question in an imperialist
country was wrong – and had been wrong too in the approach to
the Quebecois question. Because, contrary to Lenin’s advice,
the Canadian comrades did not start from “a clear notion of
historical and economic circumstances,” i.e. from an analysis
of objective class relations, but from speculations about
the moods of the masses. What inspired Comrade Dowson to move to
this wrong position was the fact that growing mass support
seemed to manifest itself for concrete demands oriented against
US imperialism. At the root of his revisionism is the same
deviation of tail-endism.
Within imperialist nations,
nationalism is one of the main ideological instruments with
which the bourgeoisie (and its petty-bourgeois hangers-on) try
to weaken and paralyse the proletarian class struggle. In the
first world war, “the Kaiser” and the “bloody Tsar”
played that role in both imperialist camps. In the second world
war, “fascism” and “western plutocracies” were used for
the same purposes. Since the late forties, with the help of the
CPs and the maoists, the European bourgeoisie is using the same
ideological weapon to confuse and divide the workers. The
“main enemy” is supposed to be US imperialism (or the Common
Market, or some other “foreign” factor. Some extreme maoists
even say today that the “main enemies” is “soviet fascist
social imperialism”) – but never the imperialist rulers of
one’s own country.
To this nationalism, communists
have always countered with the slogan: the enemy is in our own
imperialist country! It is the task of the workers of each
imperialist country to overthrow their own ruling class and its
state power, irrespective of the relative importance of that
ruling class in the imperialist hierarchy. The only way
in which the Canadian working class can decisively further the
world struggle against imperialism – including the struggle
against US imperialism – is by overthrowing Canadian
capitalism and its bourgeois state. Canadian nationalism, by
diverting attention from that task towards the supposed priority
of struggling against “predominant” US imperialism, creates
an ideological and political obstacle on the road towards class
consciousness and class organisation of the Canadian
proletariat, thereby making the overthrow of the Canadian
bourgeois state more difficult, and, incidentally, in the long
run reducing the contribution which the Canadian working class
could make towards a socialist revolution inside the USA, the
only development which can effectively and totally destroy US
imperialism.
There are no doubt some
“progressive elements” in “Canadian nationalism.” But
then, there are also “progressive elements” in proletarian
social-patriotism as well, as Trotsky points out in the Transitional
Programme. When workers say they want to defend their
imperialist fatherland, it is obviously not for the same reasons
as those which make the imperialist bourgeoisie raise the banner
of patriotism. But does one draw from that the conclusion that,
because there is “some progressive content” in workers’
social-patriotism, revolutionary Marxists should advocate
social-patriotism? Isn’t the correct conclusion rather that it
is necessary to separate the content of these
“progressive elements” (by means of concrete
immediate, democratic or transitional demands) from their form,
social-patriotism, in order to wage a more efficient war against
that reactionary form? Why should we depart from that
standard procedure in the case of English-Canadian nationalism?
The US capitalists’
stranglehold over Canadian economic life is not something
peculiar to the USA as a nation or to the US rulers. It is the
result of a specific relationship of forces in the framework of
world-wide inter-imperialist rivalries. Yesterday, the Canadian
economy was dominated by British imperialism, a domination which
was no more “progressive” than that of the US overlords.
To-morrow, it could become a big arena of contest between US,
European, Japanese and “autonomous” Canadian capitalists.
What we oppose in Canada is not “foreign monopolies,” but
monopoly capitalism tout court. What Canadian workers
should overthrow is the stranglehold of Big Business, and not
just of US Big Business. We struggle for the expropriation of
all capitalist property, not just US or foreign-owned property.
When he used the formula
“Canadians resent blatant violations of Canadian law by US
based corporations leading to loss of jobs and trade by
Canada” (p.21 of the Discussion Bulletin of the
LSA-LSO, No.5, 1972) Comrade Dowson made an additional
step of converting himself from a defender of the
“progressive” into a defender of the reactionary content of
“Canadian Nationalism.” Since when is the working class
worried by the “loss of trade” of its own imperialist
bourgeoisie? Since when do Marxists counterpose solidarity with
the trade interests of their own bourgeoisie to international
solidarity of the workers of all competing capitalist countries,
against all capitalist competitors? Since when are we worried
lest Canadian bourgeois law is violated? How can you ever make a
socialist revolution in Canada without violating bourgeois law?
Do you educate the workers of your country towards understanding
the need for a socialist revolution, if you instill in them
simultaneously worries about loss of trade by Canadian
capitalism and the sacred character of Canadian bourgeois law?
The main argument used by
Comrade Dowson to justify his tail-ending of Canadian
nationalism is the assumed inability of the Canadian bourgeoisie
to use in its own interests the nationalist sentiments
developing in certain strata of the masses, because its fate in
“inextricably bound up with the fate of US imperialism.”
This argument is completely wrong. The Japanese, West German,
British, French, Italian bourgeoisies are as conscious as the
Canadian one that “their fate is inextricably bound up with
the fate of US imperialism.” But that does not prevent them
from developing all kinds of “nationalisms” in order to
modify the relationship of forces (the way profits, burdens
and spoils are being divided) inside the imperialist
alliance. We have for years correctly analysed the
situation inside the world imperialist camp as that of
inter-imperialist rivalry and competition within the framework
of an alliance. Events during the last years, e.g. around the
“dollar crisis,” have completely confirmed the correctness
of that analysis. But it then follows that the second half of
Comrade Dowson’s formula in no way results from the first
half. On the contrary: in spite of them being conscious
of the fact that, ultimately, they have to hang together in
order not to be hung separately, the different imperialist
powers, including Canada, certainly try to use all kinds of
economic, political and ideological weapons (“Nationalism”
and “anti-Americanism” being one of them) in order to
further their own specific competitive interests and to weaken
the class struggle in their own country.
It follows that anti-US
Canadian nationalism has no automatic “anti-imperialist” or
even “anti-capitalist” thrust, as Comrade Dowson tries to
imply. It could have this only under very concrete conditions of
conscious political working class hegemony inside the
mass movement, i.e. hegemony by conscious revolutionary Marxist
forces, by the Canadian Trotskyists. To consider this hegemony
as guaranteed in advance is to be guilty of a gross
over-optimism. In reality, there will be a constant struggle
between revolutionary and reformist (i.e. objectively pro-class
collaboration and pro-bourgeois) political forces inside that
mass movement. In this struggle for political hegemony by the
revolutionary Marxists, confusion on the issue of nationalism is
going to make things easier for the petty-bourgeois reformist
and class collaborationist forces, and certainly not for the
revolutionary Marxist ones.
Just to mention one example:
nationalisation under workers control is not at all the only
possible alternative to US domination of Canadian factories.
Other ways are to strengthen “our” businessmen in their
competition against the American ones (helping them make larger
profits and therefore accepting voluntary wage restraints).
Another way again would consist in bringing in stronger
partnership with British, West-European and Japanese capital.
Still another one would be the takeover of certain
American-controlled corporations by the Canadian bourgeois
state, without workers control, in the interests of
“independent” capital accumulation by the private Canadian
imperialists. Do we consider any of these alternatives “lesser
evils” which we have to support “critically” as against US
ownership or control? If not, how can we cover that whole
complex situation by supporting “Canadian nationalism”?
The basic weakness of this
whole argumentation is its static character. It deals with the
question of Canadian nationalism exclusively from the point of
view of political forces as they are – or more correctly: as
they appear to be – to-day. But in the coming years, there
will be many shifts and upheavals in Canadian political life,
some of momentous character, as the class struggle sharpens and
the crisis of Canadian imperialism and its pluri-national state
deepens. It is unwise and unrealistic, to say the least, to
exclude under these conditions the desire or ability of sections
of the Canadian bourgeoisie to use nationalism in a
“gaullist” way, in order to canalise and divert temporarily
a mass explosion towards channels compatible with the survival
of the capitalist relations of production. To exclude that
possibility is to eliminate the difference between Canada as
imperialist country and backward semi-colonial and colonial
countries. Comrade Dowson’s grave mistakes on the question of
Canadian nationalism flow from the wrong method used by the
majority of the Canadian section’s leadership in determining
its position on Quebecois nationalism too, – a method of
tail-ending mass moods, instead of starting from an assessment
of the dynamics of class relations and class struggle.
19.
Tail-Ending Elevated to the Level of Principle
In his article Why
Guevara’s guerilla strategy has no future, Comrade Peter
Camejo does not limit himself to rewriting the history of the
Cuban revolution in order to strengthen his case against
“terrorist guevarism.” He also gives a summary of what the
“essence” of “Lenin’s concept of a combat party of the
working class” is like in his opinion. Here is this
“essence” in his own words:
“1. The party is built
around a revolutionary programme. Only those in agreement with
its Marxist programme and willing to accept its discipline in
action can be members.
“2. In the day-to-day
struggle of the working class, individual workers are
radicalised. The party seeks to recruit these workers, train
them in its programme and organisational methods, and unite
them in a single national organisation that acts in a
disciplined manner on a national scale.
“3. The party spreads into
all the oppressed layers of the population, including the
non-working-class sectors. It tries to promote mass struggles
and give the masses confidence in their own strength by
mobilising them around transitional, democratic, or immediate
demands related to their present level of consciousness.
“4. The party promotes
whatever forms of struggle are appropriate, using tactics
ranging from peaceful marches to armed struggle (including
guerilla warfare).
“5. The party seeks to lead
the working class and its allies to state power as its
fundamental goal, but does not try to substitute itself for
the masses.
“6. Each national party is
part of a single international party of world proletariat.”
(ISR, November 1972, p.33.)
What is striking about this
“essence” of the “Leninist concept of the combat party of
the working class is that there is nothing specifically
“Leninist” about it. Every single one of these six
“essential” aspects of Pete Camejo’s “concept of the
combat party” could have been gladly supported and sincerely
accepted by all the top leaders of classical pre-1914
social-democracy, with Kautsky, Bebel and their companions in
the lead.
A revolutionary party
programme? After all wasn’t the Erfurt programme of German
social-democracy corrected and accepted by Engels himself?
Accepting party discipline? What German social-democrat worthy
of that name would have rejected that? Recruiting workers
“radicalised in daily struggles”: didn’t German
social-democracy do this on a scale much wider than the Russian
pre-1914 Bolsheviks? Training them in the programme and the
organisation methods, uniting them into a single national
organisation: wasn’t that also done in an exemplary way?
Spreading to all oppressed layers and trying to promote mass
struggles and giving the masses self-confidence: who had more
success in that field than pre-1914 German social-democracy?
Using all forms of tactics, and “promoting whatever forms of
struggle are appropriate,” to the point of not even excluding
armed insurrection: Bebel and Kautsky agreed wholeheartedly. (In
the case “they” took away universal franchise, they were in
favour of insurrection). The conquest of state power? Classical
German social-democracy repeated that to be its main goal day
after day. The need to be part of an “international party of
world proletariat”: wasn’t German social-democracy the
mainstay of the Second International?
So Pete Camejo has achieved the
amazing feat of reducing Lenin’s concept of the vanguard party
to that of pre-1914 classical German social-democracy, whose big
historical triumphs are known to all. Lenin equals Kautsky: that
is the uttermost “essence” of Comrade Camejo’s new
message. This is certainly not orthodox Trotskyism, as
understood by Trotsky himself. Nor is it Leninism, as developed
by Lenin himself. But at least it gives a clearer and more
rounded expression of the kind of tail-endist current which are
developing today inside the world Trotskyist movement – and to
which Comrade Hansen, seized by his all-consuming passion for
tracking down and slaying the dangerous dragon of “rural
guerilla warfare” and “terrorist guevarism,” turns a
strangely blind eye.
What is missing from Comrade
Camejo’s definition of a Leninist combat party are precisely
the three essential differences between classical
social-democracy (i.e, Kautskyism) and Leninism.
First: in the six point
definition of Comrade Camejo, revolutionary perspectives and
revolutionary struggles are completely missing: The word
“revolution” is mentioned only once in relation with the
programme. But a party can have a revolutionary programme –
whose realisation will be postponed to the distant future,
because of the absence of a revolutionary perspectives and
revolutionary struggles.
Of course, a party cannot
artificially “create” revolutionary perspectives and
revolutionary struggles when objective conditions are not ripe
for it. This is why before 1905, the degeneration of German
social-democracy was only incipient. But once the objective
situation changes, once revolutionary perspectives are
objectively opening up, the clear understanding of these
perspectives, and the preparation of the party for the
revolutionary struggles which will inevitably occur,
becomes the first major task of revolutionaries, the key
difference between Kautsky’s centrists and Leninists. To
concentrate all the party’s effort on the preparation for the
coming revolution: that was the key aspect of Lenin’s concept
of a revolutionary combat party.
Comrade Cannon starts his
article The Vanguard Party and the World Revolution (in
Fifty Years of World Revolution 1917-1967) with
the sentence: “The greatest contribution to the arsenal of
Marxism since the death of Engels in 1895 was Lenin’s
conception of the vanguard party as the organiser and
director of the proletarian revolution.” This key aspect
of Lenin’s concept of the party is forgotten in Comrade
Camejo’s “essence.” The understanding of the revolutionary
character of the epoch, the deep assimilation of the “actuality
of the revolution,” is flesh and blood of the
revolutionary combat party which Lenin built.
Second: the relationship
between the vanguard – the party – and the working class is
presented unilaterally and mechanically. The party “Tries to
promote mass struggles ... by mobilising the masses” around
demands “related to their present level of consciousness.”
It “seeks to recruit individual workers who become radicalised
through these struggles and train them in its programme.” One
can summarise this concept as: intervening in mass struggles and
cadre building general socialist propaganda and education. But
this formula creates more questions than it answers. Does it
mean that no revolutionary struggles are possible as long as the
party has not recruited enough “radicalised workers” in its
own ranks and educated them in its programme? What is this
“present level of consciousness” of the masses? Is it always
the same? Can it shift rapidly? If yes, has the combat party to
wait till it has shifted before it “adapts” its demands? Or
can it foresee these shifts and act accordingly? In function of
what factors can it foresee these shifts? Will the “present
level of consciousness” itself not be to a certain degree a
function of the role of the “combat party” inside the mass
movement? But if one of the main purposes of the “combat
party” is to raise the level of class consciousness
of the working class, how then can the “present level of
consciousness” in itself be a decisive criterion for
determining what kind of demands the party should raise before
the masses?
Trotsky, long ago, answered
this question in a way which Comrade Camejo doesn’t seem to
have understood:
“We know that the mentality
of every class of society is determined by objective
conditions, by the productive forces, by the economic state of
the country, but this determination is not immediately
reflected. The mentality is in general backward, in relation
to the economic development ...
“The programme must express
the objective tasks of the working class rather than the
backwardness of the workers. It must reflect society as it is
and not the backwardness of the working class. It is an
instrument to overcome and vanquish the backwardness.”
(Discussion with Trotsky on The Death Agony of
Capitalism, May 1938.)
And in order not to be taken in
by any alleged distinctions between the party programme –
Trotsky has in mind here not the general programme but the
programme of transitional demands for which the party fights on
a daily basis, immediately – and the demands raised by the
Leninist combat party, Trotsky reminds us of the following:
“What can a revolutionary
party do in this situation? In the first place give a clear
honest picture of the objective situation, of the historic
tasks which flow from this situation, irrespective as to
whether or not the workers are today ripe for this. Our
tasks don’t depend on the mentality of the worker ...
We must tell the workers the truth, then we will win the best
elements.”
In other words: the function of
the Transitional Programme is not limited to
raising demands “related to the present level of
consciousness” of the masses, but to change that level of
consciousness in function of the objective needs of the class
struggle. That is the key difference between transitional
demands on the one hand, and democratic and immediate demands on
the other hand (which of course should not be neglected or
abandoned by a revolutionary party). Transitional demands form a
bridge between the present level of consciousness and the
objective historical needs for a socialist revolution. They are
transitional precisely inasmuch as they unleash such types of
struggles through which successive sectors of the masses learn
to understand the need for a socialist revolution,
i.e., overcome, in action first, and in consciousness
afterwards, the inadequacy of their class consciousness, i.e.,
the inadequacy of their “present level of consciousness.”
Obviously, if the demands
advanced by the vanguard party are unrelated to the
given level of consciousness of the masses, they will fail to
unleash mass struggles – and in that case the level of
consciousness of the masses will not be raised. But on the other
hand, if the demands simply express that given level of
consciousness, there is no raising of that level either. What is
transitional about transitional demands is precisely
the movement from the given level of consciousness to
a higher level, and not a simple adaptation to the given
level.
This key idea of the Transitional
Programme, which permeates the first pages of the
document itself and all of Trotsky’s writings of the years
1936-40 on the nature of the epoch, are completely missing from
Comrade Camejo’s “essence” of a Leninist party. This
essence is thereby reduced to tail-ending – only launching
such demands and such struggles which are “adapted” to the
given (very often backward) mentality and moods of the masses,
not to the objective necessities.
The vanguard role of the party
inside the mass movement thereby disappears. Tail-endism becomes
elevated to the level of a principle, or a fine art, and this is
served up as the “essence” of Leninism. One can be sure
that, reading Camejo, Lenin would have answered, following an
illustrious example: “Sorry, if that is the case, I’m not a
Leninist.”
Third: Another essential
dimension of the Leninist concept of the revolutionary party is
missing from Comrade Camejo’s “essence”: the dimension of revolutionary
initiative. It is true that Comrade Camejo wants the party
to “promote mass struggles by mobilising them” around a
certain number of demands. But this is formulated in such a
vague way, immediately weighed down with the consideration of
the “present level of consciousness” of these masses, and
further restricted by the warning against “the party
substituting itself for the masses,” that the absence of the
word “initiative” is by no means an accident.
The very difference between a
revolutionary party and a propaganda group is the
capacity of the former of becoming a force “influencing,
organising and directing broad masses in action.” (James P.
Cannon: The Vanguard Party and the World Revolution, op.
cit., p.357) “Promoting” mass struggles in
different ways, starting from being good trade unionists and
having cadres who are accepted by the workers in the shops as
good union leaders, is one thing. Taking the initiative to
organise and being capable of leading anti-capitalist mass
struggles as a revolutionary party, is something quite
different. As long as you have not reached that stage, you do
not have a Leninist party in the real meaning of the word. This
third key dimension of the Leninist concept of the revolutionary
party is again completely missing from Comrade Camejo’s
“essence.” One of the “essential” characteristics of the
classical centrism of the Kautsky-Bauer school was precisely
this inability of perceiving the need of revolutionary
initiatives by the party, “relationship of forces,”
“objective conditions,” “the mood of the masses”
deciding everything always in a fatalistically predetermined
way. Leninism separates itself from that type of centrism
precisely by its capacity to understand how revolutionary
initiatives can modify the relationship of forces. Of
course it cannot do so regardless of concrete conditions and
circumstances; it cannot replace scientific correct analysis of
the co-relationship of forces by adventuristic miscalculations
and voluntaristic day-dreaming. But the goal of the analysis is
always to change existing conditions in favour of the
proletarian revolution, not to adapt to the given situation. All
this Comrade Camejo doesn’t seem to include in the
“essence” of Lenin’s concept of the party ...
Footnote
1.
The following is the English translation from the French:
“Contrary to the positions
of Lenin and Trotsky on the national struggle of an oppressed
people, the tendency refused to support Quebec nationalism
unconditionally. The tendency did not accept the theory of
permanent revolution, formulated by Trotsky and confirmed by
the Russian Revolution, according to which the national
bourgeoisie of an oppressed nation (like Quebec), owing to its
dependence on world imperialism, is incapable of breaking all
imperialist ties in order to lead a national liberation
struggle against foreign oppression to a successful
conclusion. For the tendency, the dangers of an ‘easy
cooption’ of nationalism and the national struggles in
Quebec by the bourgeoisie and its parties (like the PQ)
outweighed the thoroughly revolutionary significance of the
struggle for national emancipation.”
2.
The following is the English version of the French. The first
two paragraphs were taken from the English version of Lenin’s Collected
Works, Vol. 31, pages 145 and 148. The last two
paragraphs were translated from the French as they do not appear
in the English Collected Works of Lenin.
“... the Communist Party,
as the avowed champion of the proletarian struggle to
overthrow the bourgeois yoke, must base its policy, in the
national question too, not on abstract and formal principles
but, first, on a precise appraisal of the specific historical
situation and, primarily, of economic conditions; second, on a
clear distinction between the interests of the oppressed
classes, of working and exploited people, and the general
concept of national interests as a whole, which implies the
interests of the ruling class; third, on an equally clear
distinction between the oppressed, dependent and subject
nations and the oppressing, exploiting and sovereign nations,
in order to counter the bourgeois-democratic lies that play
down this colonial and financial enslavement of the vast
majority of the world’s population by an insignificant
minority of the richest and advanced capitalist countries, a
feature characteristic of the era of finance capital and
imperialism.”
“Recognition of
internationalism hi word, and its replacement in deed by
petty-bourgeois nationalism and pacifism, in all propaganda
agitation and practical work, is very common, not only among
the parties of the Second International, but also among those
which have withdrawn from it, and often even among parties
which now call themselves communist ... Petty-bourgeois
nationalism proclaims as internationalism the mere recognition
of the equality of nations, and nothing more. Quite apart from
the fact that this recognition is purely verbal,
petty-bourgeois nationalism preserves national self-interest
intact ...”
“In the oppressed
countries, there exist two movements that each day move
further and further apart: the first is the
bourgeois-democratic nationalist movement that has a program
of political independence and bourgeois order; the other is
the movement of the poor and backward peasants and workers for
their emancipation from all forms of exploitation.
“The first attempts to lead
the second and has often succeeded to a certain extent. But
the Communist International and the parties belonging to it
must combat this tendency and seek to develop independent
class sentiments in the working masses of the colonies.”
|