Introduction
- Bourgeois ideology and proletarian class consciousness
- Proletarian class struggle and proletarian class consciousness
- The revolutionary vanguard and spontaneous mass action
- Organisation, bureaucracy and revolutionary action
- Organisational theory, revolutionary program, revolutionary practice
- Organisational theory, democratic centralism and soviet democracy
- Sociology of economism, bureaucratism and spontaneity
- Scientific intelligentsia, social science and proletarian class consciousness
- Historical pedagogy and communication of class consciousness
Introduction
A serious discussion of the
historical importance and current relevance of the Leninist
theory of organisation is possible only if one determines the
exact position of this theory in the history of Marxism – or
to be more precise, in the historical process of the unfolding
and development of Marxism. This, like any process, must be
reduced to its internal contradictions through the intimate
interrelation between the development of theory and the
development of the actual proletarian class struggle.
Approached in this way, the
Leninist theory of organisation appears as a dialectical unity
of three elements: a theory of the present relevance of
revolution for the underdeveloped countries in the imperialist
epoch (which was later expanded to apply to the entire world in
the epoch of the general crisis of capitalism); a theory of the
discontinuous and contradictory development of proletarian class
consciousness and of its most important stages, which should be
differentiated from one another; and a theory, of the essence of
Marxist theory and its specific relationship to science on the
one hand and to proletarian class struggle on the other.
Looking more closely, one
discovers that these three theories form, so to speak, the
“social foundation” of the Leninist concept of organisation,
without which it would appear arbitrary, non-materialist and
unscientific. The Leninist concept of the party is not the only
possible one. It is, however, the only possible concept of the
party which assigns to the vanguard party the historic role of
leading a revolution which is considered, in an intermediate or
long-range sense, to be inevitable. The Leninist concept of the
party cannot be separated from a specific analysis of
proletarian class consciousness, i.e., from the understanding
that political class consciousness – as opposed to
mere “trade union” or “craft” consciousness – grows
neither spontaneously nor automatically out of the objective
developments of the proletarian class struggle. [1]
And the Leninist concept of the party is based upon the premise
of a certain degree of autonomy of scientific analysis,
and especially of Marxist theory. This theory, though
conditioned by the unfolding of the proletarian class struggle
and the first embryonic beginnings of the proletarian
revolution, should not be seen as the mechanically inevitable
product of the class struggle but as the result of a theoretical
practice (or “theoretical production”) which is able to link
up and unite with the class struggle only through a prolonged
struggle. The history of the world-wide socialist revolution in
the twentieth century is the history of this prolonged process.
These three propositions
actually represent a deepening of Marxism, i.e., either of
themes that were only indicated but not elaborated upon by Marx
and Engels, or of elements of Marxist theory which were scarcely
noticed due to the delayed and interrupted publication of
Marx’s writings in the years 1880-1905. [2]
It therefore involves a further deepening of Marxist theory
brought about because of gaps (and in part contradictions) in
Marx’s analysis itself, or at least in the generally accepted
interpretation of it in the first quarter century after Marx’s
death.
What is peculiar about this
deepening of Marx’s teaching is that, setting out from
different places, it proceeds toward the same central point,
namely, to a determination of the special character of the
proletarian or socialist revolution.
In contrast to all previous
revolutions – not only the bourgeois revolutions, whose laws
of motion have been studied in great detail (in the first place
by Marx and Engels themselves), but also those revolutions which
have hitherto been far less subjected to a systematic,
generalised analysis (such as the peasant revolutions and those
of the urban petty bourgeoisie against feudalism; the uprisings
of slaves and the revolts of clan societies against slaveholding
society; the peasant revolutions that occurred as the old
Asiatic mode of production periodically disintegrated, etc.) –
the proletarian revolution of the twentieth century is
distinguished by four particular features. These give it a
specific character, but also, as Marx foresaw [3],
make it an especially difficult undertaking.
- The proletarian revolution
is the first successful revolution in the history of mankind
to be carried out by the lowest social class. This class
disposes of a potentially huge, but actually extremely
limited, economic power and is by and large excluded from
any share in the social wealth (as opposed to the mere
possession of consumer goods which are continuously used
up). Its situation is quite different from the bourgeoisie
and the feudal nobility, who seized political power when
they already held in their hands the actual economic power
of society, as well as from the slaves, who were unable to
carry through a successful revolution.
- The proletarian revolution
is the first revolution in the history of humanity aimed at
a consciously planned overthrow of existing society, i.e.,
which does not seek to restore a previous state of affairs
(as did the slave and peasant revolutions of the past), or
simply to legalise a transfer of power already achieved on
the economic field, but rather to bring into being a
completely new process, one which has never before existed
and which has been anticipated only as a “theory” or a
“program.” [4]
- Just like every other social
revolution in history, the proletarian revolution grows out
of the internal class antagonisms and the class struggle
they inevitably produce within the existing society. But
while revolutions in the past could by and large be
satisfied with pushing this class struggle forward until a
culminating point was reached – because for them it was
not a question of creating completely new and consciously
planned social relations – the proletarian revolution can
become a reality only if the proletarian class struggle
culminates in a gigantic process, stretching out over years
and decades. This process is one of systematically and
consciously overturning all human relations, and of
generalising first the independent activity of the
proletariat, and later (on the threshold of the classless
society) that of all members of society. While the triumph
of the bourgeois revolution makes the bourgeoisie into a
conservative class (which is still able to achieve
revolutionary transformations in the technical and
industrial fields, and which plays an objectively
progressive role in history for a rather long period of
time, but which pulls back from an active transformation of
social life, since in that sphere its mounting collisions
with the proletariat it exploits make it increasingly
reactionary), the conquest of power by the proletariat is not
the end but the beginning of the activity of the modern
working class in revolutionising society. This activity can
end only when it liquidates itself as a class, along with
all other classes. [5]
- In contrast to all previous
social revolutions, which by and large have taken place
within a national or an even more limited regional
framework, the proletarian revolution is by nature
international and can reach its conclusion only in the
world-wide construction of a classless society. Although it
certainly can achieve victory at first within a national
framework alone, this victory will constantly be endangered
and provisional so long as the class struggle on an
international scale has not inflicted a decisive defeat upon
capital. The proletarian revolution, then, is a world
revolutionary process, which is carried out neither in a
linear fashion nor with uniformity. The imperialist chain
breaks first at its weakest links, and the discontinuous ebb
and flow of the revolution occurs in conformity with the law
of uneven and combined development. (This is true not only
for the economy but also for the relationship of forces
between classes; the two by no means automatically
coincide,.) The Leninist theory of organisation takes into
account all these peculiarities of the proletarian
revolution. It takes into consideration the peculiarities of
this revolution in light of, among other things, the
peculiarities and contradictions in the formation of
proletarian class consciousness. Above all, it expresses
openly what Marx only intimated, and which his epigones
scarcely understood at all, namely, that there can be
neither an “automatic” overthrow of the capitalist
social order nor a “spontaneous” or “organic”
disintegration of this social order through the construction
of a socialist one. Precisely because of the uniquely
conscious character of the proletarian revolution, it
requires not only a maturity of “objective” factors (a
deepening social crisis which expresses the fact that the
capitalist mode of production has fulfilled its historic
mission), but also a maturity of so-called subjective
factors (maturity of proletarian class consciousness and of
its leadership). If these “subjective” factors are
either not present, or are present to an insufficient
extent, the proletarian revolution will not be victorious at
that point, and from its very defeat will result
the economic and social possibilities for a temporary
consolidation of capitalism. [6]
The Leninist theory of
organisation represents, then, broadly speaking, the deepening
of Marxism, applied to the basic problems of the social
superstructure (the state, class consciousness, ideology, the
party). Together with the parallel contributions of Rosa
Luxemburg and Trotsky (and, in a more limited sense of Lukacs
and Gramsci), it constitutes the Marxist science of the
subjective factor.
I. Bourgeois ideology and
proletarian class consciousness
The Marxian proposition that
“the dominant ideology of every society is the ideology of the
dominant class” appears at first glance to conflict with the
character of the proletarian revolution as the conscious
overturning of society by the proletariat, as a product of the
conscious, independent activity of the wage-earning masses. A
superficial interpretation of this proposition might lead to the
conclusion that it is utopian to expect the masses who, under
capitalism, are manipulated and exposed to the constant
onslaught of bourgeois and petty-bourgeois ideas, to be capable
of carrying out a revolutionary class struggle against this
society, let alone a social revolution, Herbert Marcuse, who
draws this conclusion, is (for the time being) simply the latest
in a long series of theoreticians who, taking as their point of
departure the Marxian definition of the ruling class, finish by
calling into question the revolutionary potential of the working
class.
The problem can be solved by
replacing the formalistic and static point of view with a
dialectical one. The Marxian proposition simply needs to be made
more “dynamic”. The dominant ideology of every society is
the ideology of the dominant class in the sense that the latter
has control over the means of ideological production which
society has at its disposal (the church, schools, mass media,
etc.) and uses these means in its own class interests. As long
as class rule is on the upswing, stable and hence hardly
questioned, the ideology of the dominant class will also
dominate the consciousness of the oppressed class. Moreover, the
exploited will, as a rule, tend to formulate the first
phases of the class struggle in terms of the formulas,
ideals and ideologies of the exploiters. [7]
However, the more the stability
of the existing society is brought into question, and the more
the class struggle intensifies, and the more the class rule of
the exploiters itself begins to waver in practice, the more will
at least sections of the oppressed class begin to free
themselves of the control of the ideas of those in power. Prior
to, and along with, the struggle for the social revolution, a
struggle goes on between the ideology of the rulers and the new
ideals of the revolutionary class. This struggle in turn
intensifies and accelerates the concrete class struggle out of
which it arose by lifting the revolutionary class to an
awareness of its historical tasks and of the immediate goals of
its struggle. Class consciousness on the part of the
revolutionary class can therefore develop out of the class
struggle in spite of and in opposition to the ideology of the
ruling class. [8]
But it is only in the
revolution itself that the majority of the oppressed can
liberate themselves from the ideology of the ruling class. [9]
For this control is exerted not only, nor even primarily,
through purely ideological manipulation and the mass
assimilation of the ruling class’ ideological production, but
above all through the actual day-to-day workings of the existing
economy and society and their effect on the consciousness of the
oppressed. (This is especially true in bourgeois society,
although parallel phenomena can be seen in all class societies.)
In capitalist society this
control is exerted through the internalisation of commodity
relations, which is closely tied to the reification of human
relations and which results from the generalised extension of
commodity production and the transformation of labour power into
a commodity, and from the generalised extension of the social
division of labour under conditions of commodity production. It
is also accomplished through the fatigue and brutalisation of
the producers through exploitation and the alienated nature of
labour, as well as through a lack of leisure time, not only in a
quantitative but also in a qualitative sense, etc. Only when the
workings of this imprisonment are blown apart by a revolution,
i.e., by a sudden, intense increase, in mass activity
outside of the confines of alienated labour – only then
can the mystifying influence of this very imprisonment upon mass
consciousness rapidly recede.
The Leninist theory of
organisation therefore attempts to come to grips with the inner
dialectic of this formation of political class consciousness,
which can develop fully only during the revolution
itself, yet only on the condition that it has already begun to
develop before the revolution. [10]
The theory does this by means of three operative categories: the
category of the working class in itself (the mass of workers);
the category of that part of the working class that is already
engaging in more than sporadic struggles and has already reached
a first level of organisation (the proletarian vanguard in the
broad sense of the word); [11]
and the category of the revolutionary organisation, which
consists of workers and intellectuals who participate in
revolutionary activities and are at least partially educated in
Marxism.
The category of “the class in
itself” is linked to the objective class concept in the
sociology of Marx, where a social layer is determined by its
objective position in the process of production independent
of its state of consciousness. (It is well known that the young
Marx – in the Communist Manifesto and in his
political wrings of 1850-1852, for instance – had put forward
a subjective concept of the class according to which the working
class becomes a class only through its struggle, i.e., by
reaching a minimum degree of class consciousness. Bukharin, in
connection with a formula from The Poverty of Philosophy,
calls this concept the concept of “the class for itself” as
opposed to the concept of the “class in itself.”) [12]
This objective concept of the class remains fundamental for
Lenin’s ideas on organisation, as it did for Engels and the
German Social Democracy under the influence of Engels, Bebel and
Kautsky. [13]
It is only because there exists
an objectively revolutionary class that can, and is periodically
obliged to, conduct an actual revolutionary class struggle, and
it is only in relation to such an actual class struggle, that
the concept of a revolutionary vanguard party (including that of
professional revolutionaries) has any scientific meaning at all,
as Lenin himself explicitly observed. [14]
All revolutionary activity not related to this class struggle
leads at best to a party nucleus, but not to a party. This runs
the risk of degenerating into sectarian, subjective
dilettantism. According to Lenin’s concept of organisation,
there is no self-proclaimed vanguard. Rather, the vanguard must
win recognition as a vanguard (i.e., the historical right to act
as a vanguard) through its attempts to establish revolutionary
ties with the advanced part of the class and its actual
struggle.
The category of “advanced
workers” stems from the objectively inevitable stratification
of the working class. It is a function of their distinct
historical origin, as well as their distinct position in the
social process of production and their distinct class
consciousness.
The formation of the working
class as an objective category is itself an historical process.
Some sections of the working class are the sons, grandsons, and
great-grandsons of urban wage labourers; others are the sons and
grandsons of agricultural labourers and landless peasants, Still
others are only first or second generation descendants of a
petty bourgeoisie that owned some means of production (peasants,
artisans, etc.). Part of the working class works in large
factories where both the economic and the social relations give
rise to at least an elementary class consciousness
(consciousness that “social questions” can be solved only
through collective activity and organisation). Another part
works in small or medium-sized factories in industry or in the
so-called service sectors, where economic self-confidence as
well as an understanding of the necessity for broad mass actions
flow much less easily from the objective situation than in the
large industrial plant. Some sections of the working class have
been living in big cities for a long time. They have been
literate for a long time and have several generations of
trade-union organisation and political and cultural education
behind them (through youth organisations, the workers press,
labour education, etc.). Still others live in small towns or
even in the countryside. (This was true into the late 1930s, for
instance, for a significant number of European miners.) These
workers have little or no collective social life, scarcely any
trade-union experience, and have received no political or
cultural education at all in the organised workers movement.
Some sectors of the working class are born from nations which
were independent for a thousand years, and whose ruling class
oppressed for long periods other nations. Other workers are born
from nations which fought for decades or centuries for their
national freedom – or who lived in slavery or serfdom no more
than one hundred years ago. If one adds to all these historical
and structural differences the various personal abilities of
each wage worker – not just differences in intelligence and
ability to generalise from immediate experiences, but
differences in the amount of energy, strength of character:
combatively and self-assurance too – then one understands that
the stratification of the working class into various layers,
depending on the degree of class consciousness, is an inevitable
phenomenon in the history of the working class itself. It is
this historical process of becoming a class which, at a given
point in time, is reflected in the various degrees of
consciousness within the class.
The category of the
revolutionary party stems from the fact that Marxian socialism
is a science which, in the final analysis, can be
completely assimilated only in an individual and not in a
collective manner. Marxism constitutes the culmination (and in
part also the dissolution) of at least three classical social
sciences: classical German philosophy, classical political
economy, and classical French political science (French
socialism and historiography). Its assimilation presupposes at
least an understanding of the materialist dialectic, historical
materialism, Marxian economic theory and the critical history of
modern revolutions and of the modern labour movement. Such an
assimilation is necessary if it is to be able to function, in
its totality, as an instrument for analysing social reality and
as the compilation of the experiences of a century of
proletarian class struggle. The notion that this colossal sum of
knowledge and information could somehow spontaneously flow from
working at a lathe or a calculating machine is absurd. [15]
The fact that as a science
Marxism is an expression of the highest degree in the
development of proletarian class consciousness means simply that
it is only through an individual process of selection
that the best, most experienced, the most intelligent and the
most combative members of the proletariat are able to directly
and independently acquire this class consciousness in its most
potent form. To the extent that this acquisition is an
individual one, it also becomes accessible to other social
classes and layers (above all, the revolutionary intelligentsia
and the students). [16]
Any other approach can lead only to an idealisation of the
working class – and ultimately of capitalism itself.
Of course it must always be
remembered that Marxism could not arise independently of the
actual development of bourgeois society and of the class
struggle that was inevitably unfolding within it. There is an
inextricable tie between the collective, historical experience
of the working class in struggle and its scientific working out
of Marxism as collective, historical class consciousness in its
most potent form. But to maintain that scientific socialism is
an historical product of the proletarian class struggle is not
to say that all or even most members of this class can, with
greater or lesser ease, reproduce this knowledge. Marxism is not
an automatic product of the class struggle and class experience
but a result of scientific, theoretical production. Such an
assimilation is made possible only through participation in that
process of production; and this process is by definition an individual
one, even though it is only made possible through the
development social forces of production and class contradictions
under capitalism.
II. Proletarian class
struggle and proletarian class consciousness
The process whereby the
proletarian mass, the proletarian vanguard and the revolutionary
party are united depends on the elementary proletarian class
struggle growing over into revolutionary class struggle
– the proletarian revolution – and on the effects this has
on the wage-earning masses. Class struggle has taken place for
thousands of years without those who struggled being aware of
what they were doing. Proletarian class struggle was conducted
long before there was a socialist movement, let alone scientific
socialism. Elementary class struggle – strikes, work stoppages
around wage demands or for shorter working hours and other
improvements in working conditions – leads to elementary forms
of class organisation (mutual aid funds, embryonic trade
unions), even if these are short-lived. (It also gives rise to a
general socialist ideal among many workers.) Elementary
class struggle, elementary class organisation and elementary
class consciousness are born, then, directly out of action,
and only the experience arising out of that action is able to
develop and accelerate consciousness. It is a general law of
history that only through action are broad masses able
to elevate their consciousness.
But even in its most elementary
form, the spontaneous class struggle of the wage earners under
capitalism leaves behind a residue in the form of a consciousness
crystallised in a process of continuous organisation. Most
of the mass is active only during the struggle; after the
struggle it will sooner or later retreat into private life
(i.e., “into the struggle for existence”). What
distinguishes the workers vanguard from this mass is the fact
that even during a lull in the struggle it does not abandon the
front lines of the class struggle but continues the war, so to
speak, “by other means”? It attempts to solidify the
resistance funds generated in the struggle into ongoing
resistance funds – i.e., into unions. [17]
By publishing workers newspapers and organising educational
groups for workers, it attempts to crystallise and heighten the
elementary class consciousness generated in the struggle. It
thus helps give form to a factor of continuity, as opposed to
the necessarily discontinuous action of the mass [18],
and to a factor of consciousness, as opposed to the spontaneity
of the mass movement in and of itself.
However, advanced workers are
driven to continuous organisation and growing class
consciousness less by theory, science, or an intellectual grasp
of the social whole than by the practical knowledge acquired in
struggle. Since the struggle shows [19]
that the dissolving of the resistance funds after each strike
damages the effectiveness of the strike and the working sums in
hand, attempts are made to go over to the permanent strike fund.
Since experience shows an occasional leaflet to have less effect
than a regular newspaper, the workers press is born.
Consciousness arising directly out of the practical experience
of struggle is empirical and pragmatic consciousness,
which can enrich action to a certain extent, but which is far
inferior to the effectiveness, of a scientifically global
consciousness, i.e., of theoretical understanding.
Based on its general
theoretical understanding the revolutionary vanguard
organisation can consolidate and enrich this higher
consciousness, provided it is able to establish ties to the
class struggle, i.e., provided it does not shrink from the hard
test of verifying theory in practice, of reuniting theory and
practice. From the point of view of mature Marxism – as well
as that of Marx himself and Lenin – a “true” theory
divorced from practice is as much an absurdity as a
“revolutionary practice” that is not founded on a scientific
theory. This in no way diminishes the decisive importance and
absolute necessity for theoretical production. It simply
emphasises the fact that wage-earning masses and revolutionary
individuals, proceeding from different starting points and with
a different dynamic, can bring about the unity of theory and
practice.
This process can be summarised
in the following diagram:
masses: |
—> |
action |
—> |
experience |
—> |
consciousness |
|
advanced workers: |
—> |
experience |
—> |
consciousness |
—> |
action |
|
revolutionary nuclei: |
—> |
consciousness |
—> |
action |
—> |
experience |
If we rearrange this diagram so
that certain conclusions can be drawn from it, we get the
following:
masses: |
—> |
action |
—> |
experience |
—> |
consciousness |
|
revolutionary nuclei: |
—> |
consciousness |
—> |
action |
—> |
experience |
|
advanced workers: |
—> |
experience |
—> |
consciousness |
—> |
action |
This formal diagram reveals a
series of conclusions about the dynamics of class consciousness
which were already anticipated in the analysis but which only
now obtain their full value. The collective action of the
advanced workers (the “natural leaders” of the working class
in the shops) is, relatively speaking, more difficult to attain
because it can be aroused neither through pure conviction (as
with the revolutionary nuclei) nor through purely spontaneous
explosiveness (as with the broad masses). It is precisely the
struggle experience – the important motivating factor
in the actions of the advanced workers – that makes them much
more careful and cautious before they undertake action on a
broad scale. They have already digested the lessons of past
actions and know that an explosion is not at all sufficient for
them to be able to reach their goal. They have fewer illusions
about the strength of the enemy (not to mention his
“generosity”) and about the durability of the mass movement.
The greatest “temptation” of economism can be traced to this
very point.
To summarise: the building of
the revolutionary class party is the merging of the
consciousness of the revolutionary nuclei with that of the
advanced workers. The ripening of a pre-revolutionary situation
(of potentially revolutionary explosion) is the merging of
action by the broad masses with that of the advanced workers. A
revolutionary situation – i.e., the possibility of a
revolutionary conquest of power – arises when a merging of actions
by the vanguard and the masses with the consciousness
of the vanguard and revolutionary layers has been accomplished. [20]
For the broad masses, the elementary class struggle arising from
the contradictions of the capitalist mode of production is
always kindled only by matters of immediate concern. The same is
true for all mass actions, even political ones. Thus the problem
of the broad mass struggle growing over into a revolutionary one
depends not only on a quantitative factor, but also on a
qualitative one. This requires the existence of sufficiently
advanced workers within the masses or the mass movement who, on
the basis of the stage of consciousness they have already
reached, are capable of sweeping broader masses into action
around objectives that challenge the continued existence of
bourgeois society and the capitalist mode of production.
This also highlights the
central importance of transitional demands [21],
the strategic position of advanced workers already trained in
propagating these transitional demands, and the historical
importance of the revolutionary organisation, which alone is
capable of working out a comprehensive program of transitional
demands corresponding to the objective historical conditions, as
well as to the subjective needs, of the broadest layers of the
mass. A successful proletarian revolution is only possible
if all these factors are successfully combined.
We have already stated that
Lenin’s theory of organisation is, in fact, above all a theory
of revolution. To have misunderstood this is the great weakness
of Rosa Luxemburg’s polemic against Lenin in 1903-1904. It is
characteristic that the concept of centralisation which is
attacked in the essay Organisational Question of Social
Democracy is – and this is clear if it is read
attentively – a purely organisational one. (Yet while it is
attacked, it is also confirmed. On this point modern
“Luxemburgists” ought to read their “Rosa” more
carefully and more thoroughly!) Lenin is accused of advocating
an “ultra-centralist” line, of dictating the composition of
local party committees, and of wishing to stymie any initiative
by lower party units. [22]
When we turn to the Leninist
theory of organisation as developed by Lenin himself, however,
we see that the emphasis is by no means upon the formal,
organisational side of centralisation but upon its political
and social function. At the heart of What is to Be
Done? is the concept of the transformation of
proletarian class consciousness into political class
consciousness by means of a comprehensive political activity
that raises and, from a Marxist point of view, answers all
questions of internal and external class relations:
“In reality, it is possible
to ‘raise the activity of the working masses’ only
when this activity is not restricted to ‘political
agitation on an economic basis.’ A basic condition for the
necessary expansion of political agitation is the organisation
of comprehensive political exposure. In no way
except by means of such exposures con the masses be trained in
political consciousness and revolutionary activity.”
And further:
The consciousness of the
working masses cannot be genuine class consciousness, unless the
workers learn, from concrete, and above all from topical,
political facts and events to observe every other
social class in all the manifestations of its
intellectual, ethical, and political life; unless they learn to
apply in practice the materialist analysis and the materialist
estimate of all aspects of the life and activity of all
classes, strata, and groups of the population. Those who
concentrate the attention, observation, and consciousness of the
working class exclusively, or even mainly, upon itself alone are
not Social Democrats; for the self knowledge of the
working class is indissolubly bound up, not solely with a fully
clear theoretical understanding – it would be even truer to
say, not so much with the theoretical, as with the practical,
understanding – of the relationships between all the
various classes of modern society, acquired through the
experiences of political life. [23]
And it is for the same reason
that Lenin emphasises so strongly the absolute necessity for the
revolutionary party to make all progressive demands and
movements of all oppressed social layers and classes
its own – even “purely democratic” ones. The central
strategic plan advanced by Lenin in What is to Be Done?
[24] is therefore one of
party agitation that unites all elementary, spontaneous,
dispersed and “merely” local or sectional protests, revolts
and movements of resistance. The emphasis of centralisation
clearly lies in the political and not in the formal,
organisational sphere. The aim of formal organisational
centralisation is only to make possible the realisation of this
strategic plan.
Although she does not recognise
this essence of Lenin’s “centralism,” Luxemburg is
compelled in her polemic to indirectly counterpose to it another
conception of the formation of political class consciousness and
the preparation of revolutionary situations. Her doing so
emphasises even more poignantly how utterly wrong she was in
this debate. Luxemburg’s concept that “the proletarian army
is recruited and becomes aware of its objectives in the course
of the struggle itself” [25]
has been completely refuted by history. In even the broadest,
longest and most vigorous of workers struggles, the working
masses have not gained a clear understanding of the tasks of the
struggle, or did so only to an insufficient degree. (One need
only recall the French general strikes of 1936 and 1968, the
struggles of the German workers from 1918 to 1923, the great
struggles of the Italian workers in 1920, 1948 and 1969, as well
as the prodigious class struggles in Spain from 1931 to 1937, to
mention only these four European countries.)
Experience in struggle is by no
means sufficient for clarity on the tasks of a broad
pre-revolutionary, or even a revolutionary, mass struggle to be
attained. Not only, of course, are these tasks connected to the
immediate motives that set off the struggle, but they can be
grasped only by means of a comprehensive analysis of the overall
social development, of the historical position achieved by the
capitalist mode of production and its internal contradictions,
and of the national and international relationship of forces
between classes. Without protracted and consistent preparation,
without the education of hundreds and thousands of advanced
workers in the spirit of a revolutionary program, and without
the practical experience accumulated over the years by these
advanced workers through attempting to bring this program to the
broad masses, it would be absolutely illusory to assume that
suddenly, overnight so to speak, with the mere aid of mass actions,
a consciousness equal to the demands of the historical situation
could be created among these broad masses.
Actually, one could turn
Luxemburg’s proposition around and say that the proletarian
army will never reach its historic objectives if the
necessary education, schooling and testing of a proletarian
vanguard in the working out and agitational application of the
revolutionary program in struggle has not taken place before
the outbreak of the broadest mass struggles, which by themselves
create only the possibility of the broad masses
attaining revolutionary consciousness. That is the tragic lesson
of the German revolution after the first world war, which was
crushed precisely because of the lack of such a trained
vanguard.
The objective of Lenin’s
strategic plan is to create such a vanguard through an organic
union of individual revolutionary nuclei with the vanguard of
the proletariat. Such a fusion is impossible without a
comprehensive political activity that takes the
advanced workers beyond the confines of a horizon limited to the
trade union or the factory. Empirical data available to us today
confirm that Lenin’s party, before and during the revolution
of 1905 and after the mass movement began to pick up again in
1912, was in fact such a party. [26]
To fully grasp the profoundly
revolutionary nature of Lenin’s strategic plan, it must be
approached from yet another point of view. Any concept based on
the probability, if not the inevitability, of a revolution
occurring in the not too distant future, must inevitably deal
with the question of a direct collision with state power, i.e.,
the question of the conquest of political power. As soon as this
difficulty is built into the concept, however, the result is one
more argument in favour of centralisation. Lenin and Luxemburg
agreed that capitalism itself and the bourgeois state exert, a
powerful centralising influence on modern society [27],
and that it is in turn absolutely illusory to think that this
centralised state power can be gradually dismantled, as for
instance a wall can be taken apart brick by brick.
In the final analysis, the
ideological essence of the reformism and revisionism rejected by
Luxemburg and Lenin with equal passion [28]
was rooted in the illusion that this could be done. Once the
question of the conquest of state power is no longer placed far
off in the distance, however, but is recognised to be an
objective for the near or not-too-distant future, the
revolutionary is immediately confronted with the question of the
means necessary for achieving the revolutionary conquest of
power. Here again Luxemburg misconstrued the import of
Lenin’s purely polemical use of the notion of “Jacobins
inseparably linked to the organisation of the class-conscious
proletariat.” What Lenin meant with this idea was certainly
not a brand of Blanquist conspirators but an advanced group
oriented, like the Jacobins, toward an unremitting attempt to
carry out the revolutionary tasks, one that does not permit
itself to be diverted from concentrating on these tasks
by the inevitable conjunctural ebb and flow of the mass
movement.
Yet to do justice to Luxemburg
it must be added that, in the first place, she took up – in
fact had to take up – this question from a different
historical viewpoint since, by 1904, she was already influenced
more by German than by Russian or Polish reality; and second,
that she completely drew the necessary conclusions in the
Leninist sense as soon as it became clear that in Germany, too
the coming of the revolution was an immediate possibility. [29]
The young Trotsky likewise made
a serious error in his polemic against Lenin when he reproached
him for this “substitutionism,” i.e., the replacement of the
initiative of the working class with that of the party alone. [30]
If we remove the core of this reproach from its polemical shell,
we find here too an idealistic, inadequate conception of the
evolution of the class consciousness of the proletariat:
“Marxism teaches that the interests of the proletariat are
determined by its objective conditions of life. These interests
are so powerful and so unavoidable that they eventually (!)
compel the proletariat to bring them into the scope of its
consciousness, i.e., to make the realisation of its objective
interests into its subjective interest.” [31]
Today it is easy to see what a naively fatalistic optimism was
concealed in this inadequate analysis. Immediate interests are
here put on the same level with historical interests, i.e., with
the unravelling of the most complex questions of political
tactics and strategy. The hope that the proletariat will
“eventually” recognise its historical interests seems rather
shallow when compared to the historical catastrophes that have
arisen because, in the absence of an adequate revolutionary
leadership, the proletariat was not even able to accomplish the
revolutionary tasks of the here and now.
The same naive optimism is even
more strikingly manifested in the following passage from the
same polemic:
The revolutionary social
democrat is convinced not only of the inevitable (!) growth of
the political party of the proletariat, but also of the
inevitable (!) victory of the ideas of revolutionary
socialism within this party. The first proof lies in the fact
that the development of bourgeois society spontaneously leads
the proletariat to politically demarcate itself; the second in
the fact that the objective tendencies and the tactical problems
of this demarcation find their best, fullest and deepest
expression in revolutionary socialism, i.e., Marxism. [32]
This quotation makes clear that
what the young Trotsky was championing in his polemic against
Lenin was the “old, tested tactic” and the naive “belief
in the inevitability of progress” à la Bebel and Kautsky
which prevailed in the international Social Democracy from the
time of Marx’s death until the first world war. Lenin’s
concept of class consciousness was incomparably richer, more
contradictory and more dialectical precisely because it was
based on a keen grasp of the relevance of the revolution for the
present (not “finally some day” but in the coming years). To
round out the historical development it must be added that
following the outbreak of the Russian revolution in 1917,
Trotsky fully adopted Lenin’s analysis of the formation of
proletarian class consciousness and hence also Lenin’s theory
of organisation, and until his death he stubbornly defended them
against all sceptics and arch-pessimists (who claimed to detect
in them the “embryo” of Stalinism). Thus he wrote in his
last, unfinished manuscript:
A colossal factor in the
maturity of the Russian proletariat in February or March 1917
was Lenin. He did not fall from the skies. He personified the
revolutionary tradition of the working class. For Lenin’s
slogans to find their way to the masses, there had to exist
cadres, even though numerically small at the beginning; there
had to exist the confidence of the cadre in the leadership, a
confidence based upon the entire experience of the past. To
cancel these elements from one’s calculations is simply to
ignore the living revolution, to substitute for it an
abstraction, the “relationship of forces,” because the
development of the revolution precisely consists of this, that
the relationship of forces keeps incessantly and rapidly
changing under the impact of the changes in the consciousness of
the proletariat, the attraction of backward layers to the
advanced, the growing assurance of the class in its own
strength. The vital mainspring in this process is the party,
just as the vital mainspring in the mechanism of the party is
its leadership. [33]
III. The revolutionary
vanguard and spontaneous mass action
It would be a great injustice
to Lenin to characterise his life work as a systematic
“underestimation” of the importance of spontaneous mass
actions as opposed to their “appreciation” by Luxemburg or
Trotsky. Apart from polemical passages, which can only be
understood when seen in context, Lenin welcomed huge,
spontaneous outbreaks of mass strikes and demonstrations just as
enthusiastically and just as explicitly as Rosa Luxemburg and
Trotsky. [34] Only the
Stalinist bureaucracy falsified Leninism with its increasing
distrust of spontaneous mass movements – which after all is
characteristic of any bureaucracy.
Luxemburg is completely correct
to say that the outbreak of a proletarian revolution cannot be
“predetermined” by the calendar, and nothing to the contrary
will ever be found in Lenin. Lenin, like Luxemburg, was
convinced that these elemental mass explosions, without which a
revolution is unthinkable, can neither be “organised”
according to rules nor “commanded” by a row of disciplined
non-commissioned officers. Lenin, like Luxemburg, was convinced
of the mighty arsenal of creative energy, resourcefulness and
initiative that a truly broad mass action unfurls and will
always unfurl.
The difference between the
Leninist theory of organisation and the so-called theory of
spontaneity – which can be attributed to Luxemburg only with
important reservations – is thus to be found not in an
underestimation of mass initiative but in an understanding of
its limitations. Mass initiative is capable of many
magnificent accomplishments. But by itself it is not able to
draft, in the course of the struggle, a complete, comprehensive
program for a socialist revolution touching upon all social
questions (not to mention socialist reconstruction); nor is it
alone capable of bringing about a sufficient centralisation of
forces to make possible the downfall of a centralised state
power with its repressive apparatus resting on a full
utilisation of the advantages of its “inside lines” of
communication. In other words, the limitations of mass
spontaneity begin with the understanding that a victorious
socialist revolution cannot be improvised. And
“pure” mass spontaneity always boils down to improvisation.
What is more, “pure”
spontaneity exists only in books containing fairy tales about
the workers movement – but not in its real history. What is
understood by “spontaneity of the masses” are movements that
have not been planned out in detail ahead of time by some
central authority. What is not to be understood by
“spontaneity of the masses” are movements that take place
without “political influence from the outside.” Scratch off
the blue coat of an ostensibly “spontaneous movement” and
you will find the unmistakable residue of a bright red veneer.
Here a member of a “vanguard” group who set off a
“spontaneous” strike. There a former member of another
“left-deviationist” affiliation, who has long since left it
but who received sufficient mental equipment to be able, in an
explosive situation, to react with lightning speed while the
anonymous mass was still hesitating.
In one case, we will be able to
detect in “spontaneous” action the fruits of years of
“underground activity” by a trade-union opposition, or a
rank-and-file group; in another case, the result of contacts
that, for a rather long period of time, have patiently – and
without apparent success – been nurtured by shop colleagues in
a neighbouring city (or a neighbouring factory) where the
“left- wingers” are stronger. In the class struggle too
there is no such thing as a goose “spontaneously” falling
from heaven already cooked.
Thus, what differentiates
“spontaneous” actions from the “intervention of the
vanguard,” is not at all that in the former everyone in the
struggle has reached the same level of consciousness, whereas in
the latter “the vanguard” is distinct from “the mass.”
What differentiates the two forms of action is also not that in
“spontaneous” actions no solutions have been carried into
the proletariat from “outside,” while an organised vanguard
relates to the elementary demands of the mass “in an elitist
fashion,” “imposing” a program upon it. Never have there
been “spontaneous” actions without some kind of influence
from vanguard elements. The difference between “spontaneous”
actions and those in which “the revolutionary vanguard
intervenes” is essentially that in “spontaneous” actions the
nature of the intervention of the vanguard elements is
unorganised, improvised, intermittent and unplanned
(occurring by chance in this plant, that district, or that
city), while the existence of a revolutionary organisation makes
it possible to co-ordinate, plan, consciously synchronise, and
continuously shape this intervention of the vanguard elements in
the “spontaneous” mass struggle. Nearly all the requirements
of Leninist “supercentralism” are based on this and this
alone.
Only an incorrigible fatalist
(i.e., a mechanical determinist) could be convinced that all
mass explosions had to take place on a given day just
because they broke out on that day, and that, conversely, in all
cases where mass explosions did not occur it was because they
were not possible. Such a fatalistic attitude (common to the
Kautsky-Bauer school of thought) is in reality a caricature of
the Leninist theory of organisation. In any case, it is
characteristic that many opponents of Leninism, who in opposing
Lenin have so much to say about “mass spontaneity,” at the
same time fall into this vulgar, mechanical determinism without
realising how much it contradicts their “high esteem” for
“mass spontaneity.”
If, on the other hand, one
proceeds from the inevitability of periodic spontaneous mass
explosions (which occur when socio-economic contradictions have
ripened to the point where the capitalist mode of production in
fact has to periodically produce such prerevolutionary
crises), then one has to understand that it is impossible to
determine the exact moment when this will happen since thousands
of minor incidents, partial conflicts and accidental occurrences
could play an important role in determining it. For this reason,
a revolutionary vanguard which at decisive moments is able to
concentrate its own forces on the “weakest link,” is
incomparably more effective than the diffuse performance of
large numbers of advanced workers who lack this ability to
concentrate their forces. [35]
The two greatest workers
struggles to take place in the West – the French May 1968 and
the Italian fall 1969 – entirely confirmed these views. Both
began with “spontaneous” struggles prepared neither by the
trade unions nor by the big social-democratic or “communist”
parties. In both cases individual, radical workers and students
or revolutionary nuclei played a decisive role in here or there
triggering a first explosion and providing the working masses
with the opportunity to learn from an “exemplary
experience.” In both cases millions upon millions came into
the struggle – up to ten million wage earners in France, up to
fifteen million in Italy. This is more than ever before seen –
even during the greatest class struggles following the first
world war.
In both cases the spontaneous
tendency demonstrated by the workers went way beyond the
“economism” of a purely economic strike. In France this was
attested to by the factory occupations and numerous partial
initiatives, in Italy not only by huge street demonstrations and
the raising of political demands, but also by the embryonic
manifestation of a tendency toward self-organisation at the
point of production, i.e., by the attempt to take the first step
toward establishing dual power: the election of delegati di
reparto. (In this sense, the vanguard of the Italian
working class was more advanced than the French, and it drew the
first important historical lessons from the French May. [36])
But in neither case did these powerful, spontaneous mass actions
succeed in overthrowing the bourgeois state apparatus and the
capitalist mode of production, or even in advancing a mass
understanding of the objectives that would have made such an
overthrow possible within a short period of time.
To recall Trotsky’s metaphor
from The History of theRussian Revolution: the
powerful steam evaporated for lack of a piston that would have
compressed it at the decisive moment. [37]
Certainly, in the final analysis, the driving force is the
steam, i.e., the energy of mass mobilisation and mass struggle,
and not the piston itself. Without this steam the piston remains
a hollow shell. Yet without this piston even the most intense
steam is wasted and accomplishes nothing. This is the
quintessence of the Leninist theory of organisation.
IV. Organisation,
bureaucracy and revolutionary action
There is a difficulty in this
connection, however, which Lenin, during the years of the most
heated disputes with the Mensheviks, recognised either not at
all (1903-1905) or only to an insufficient degree (1908-1914).
And it is here that the full value of the historic work of
Trotsky and Rosa Luxemburg becomes clear in facilitating an
understanding of the dialectical formula “working class –
advanced workers – workers party.”
A vanguard party and a certain separation
between the party and the mass are made necessary precisely
because of the inevitably inadequate level of class
consciousness on the part of broad working masses. As Lenin
repeatedly stressed, this is a complex dialectical relationship
– a unity of separation and integration – which totally
conforms to the historical peculiarities of the revolutionary
struggle for a socialist revolution.
This separate party, however,
originates within bourgeois society which, with its
inherent features of a universal division of labour and
commodity production, tends to bring about a reification of all
human relations. [38]
This means that the building of a party apparatus separated from
the working masses involves the danger of this apparatus
becoming autonomous. When this danger develops beyond an
embryonic stage, the tendency arises for the self-preservation
of the apparatus to become an end in itself, rather than a means
to an end (successful proletarian class struggle).
This is the root of the
degeneration of both the Second and the Third Internationals,
i.e., the subordination of the mass social-democratic as well as
the Communist parties of Western Europe to conservative,
reformist bureaucracies which, in their day-to-day practice,
have become part of the status quo. [39]
Bureaucracy in workers
organisations is a product of the social division of labour,
i.e., of the inability of the working masses, who are largely
excluded from the cultural and theoretical process of production
under capitalism, to themselves regularly take care of all the
tasks which must be dealt with within the framework of their
organisation. Attempts to do this anyway, as was often done at
the onset of the workers movement, provide no solution because
this division of labour completely corresponds to material
conditions and is in no way invented by wicked careerists.
If these conditions are overlooked, primitivism, ignorance and
the brawling it produces will place the same limitations on the
movement as would otherwise be set by the bureaucracy. Having
taken a different point of departure here – that of
organisational technique instead of the level of
consciousness – we have run up against the same problem which
we had already cleared up earlier: namely, that it would be
giving the capitalist mode of production too much credit to
assume it to be a perfect school for preparing the proletariat
for independent activity, or that it automatically creates the
ability of the working masses to spontaneously recognise and
achieve all the objectives and organisational forms of their own
liberation.
Lenin, in his first debate with
the Mensheviks, very much underestimated the danger of the
apparatus becoming autonomous and of the bureaucratisation of
the workers parties. He proceeded from the assumption that the
danger of opportunism in the modern labour movement was a threat
coming mainly from petty-bourgeois academicians and
petty-bourgeois “pure trade unionists.” He made fun of the
struggle of many of his comrades against the danger of
“bureaucratism.” Actually, history showed that the greatest
source of opportunism in the Social Democracy before the first
world war came from neither the academicians nor the “pure
trade unionists” but from the social-democratic party
bureaucracy itself i.e., from a practice of “legalism”
limited on the one hand to electoral and parliamentary activity,
and on the other to a struggle for immediate reforms of an
economic and trade union nature. (To merely describe this
practice is to confirm how much it resembles that of today’s
West European Communist parties!)
Trotsky and Luxemburg
recognised this danger more accurately and earlier than Lenin.
As early as 1904 Luxemburg expressed the thought that a
“difference between the eager attack of the mass and the
[overly] prudent position of the Social Democracy” was
possible. [40] The
thought is hardly expressed before it is discarded; the only
possible validity it might have would be in the imaginary case
of an “overcentralization” of the party along Leninist
lines. Two years later Trotsky already expresses this with more
precision:
The European Socialist parties,
particularly the largest of them, the German Social-Democratic
Party, have developed their conservatism in proportion as the
masses have embraced socialism and the more these masses have
become organised and disciplined. As a consequence of this,
Social Democracy as an organisation embodying the political
experience of the proletariat may at a certain moment become a
direct obstacle to open conflict between the workers and
bourgeois reaction. In other words, the propagandist-socialist
conservatism of the proletarian parties may at a certain moment
hold back the direct struggle of the proletariat for power. [41]
This prognosis has been
tragically confirmed by history. Lenin did not yet see this
until the eve of the first world war, whereas the German left
had long before shed its illusions about the social-democratic
party administration. [42]
V. Organisational theory,
revolutionary program, revolutionary practice
After the traumatic shock
suffered by Lenin on August 4, 1914, however, he too made a
decisive step forward on this question. From then on, the
question of organisation became one not only of function but
also of content. It is no longer simply a question of
contrasting “the organisation” in general to
“spontaneity” in general, as Lenin frequently does in What
is to Be Done? and in One Step Forward, Two
Steps Backward. Now it is a question of carefully
distinguishing between an objectively conservative organisation
and an objectively revolutionary one. This distinction is made
according to objective criteria (revolutionary program,
bringing this program to the masses, revolutionary practice,
etc.), and the spontaneous combativity of the masses is
consciously preferred to the actions or even the existence of
conservative reformist mass organisations. “Naïve”
organisational fetishists might claim that after 1914 Lenin went
over to the Luxemburgist view of “spontaneism” when, in
conflicts between “unorganised masses” and the
social-democratic organisation, he systematically defends the
former against the latter, or accuses the latter of betraying
the former. [43] Lenin
now even regards the destruction of conservatised organisations
as an inescapable prerequisite for the emancipation of the
proletariat. [44]
Yet the correction, or better
yet completion, of his theory of organisation, which Lenin
undertook after 1914 was not a step backward to the worship of
“pure” spontaneity, but rather a step forward toward
distinguishing between the revolutionary party and
organisation in general. Now, instead of saying that the purpose
of the party is to develop the political class consciousness of
the working class, the formula becomes much more precise: The
function of the revolutionary vanguard consists in developing revolutionary
consciousness in the vanguard of the working class. The
building of the revolutionary class party is the process whereby
the program of the socialist revolution is fused with the
experience the majority of the advanced workers have acquired in
struggle. [45]
This elaboration and expansion
of the Leninist theory of organisation following the outbreak of
the first world war goes hand in hand with an expansion of the
Leninist concept of the relevance of revolution to the present.
Although before the year 1914 this was for Lenin limited by and
large to Russia, after 1914 it was extended to all of Europe.
(After the Russian revolution of 1905 Lenin had already
recognised the immediate potential for revolutions in the
colonies and semi-colonies.) Consequently, the validity of the
Leninist “strategic plan” for the imperialist countries of
Western Europe today is closely tied to the question of the
nature of the historical epoch in which we live. From the
standpoint of historical materialism, one is justified in
deriving a conception of the party from the “present potential
for revolution” only if one proceeds from the assumption –
correct and probable, in our estimation – that beginning with
the first world war, and no later than the Russian October
revolution, the world-wide capitalist system entered an epoch of
historic structural crisis [46]
which must periodically lead to revolutionary
situations. If, on the other hand, one assumes that we are still
in an ascending stage of capitalism as a world system, then such
a conception would have to be rejected as being completely
“voluntaristic.” For what is decisive in the Leninist
strategic plan is certainly not revolutionary propaganda
– which, of course, revolutionaries have to carry out even in
non-revolutionary periods – but its focus on revolutionary actions
breaking out in the near or not distant future. Even in the
ascending epoch of capitalism such actions were possible (cf.
the Paris Commune), but only as unsuccessful exceptions. Under
such conditions, building a party by concentrating efforts on
preparing to effectively participate in such actions would
hardly make sense.
The difference between a
“workers party” in general (referring to its membership or
even its electoral supporters) and a revolutionary workers party
(or the nucleus of such a party) is to be found not only in
program or objective social functions (which is to promote, not
pacify, all objectively revolutionary mass actions, or all
challenges and forms of action that attack and call into
question the essence of the capitalist mode of production and
the bourgeois state), but also in its ability to find a suitable
pedagogical method enabling it to bring this program to
ever-growing numbers of workers.
One can go further, however,
and formulate the question more sharply: Is the danger of the
apparatus becoming autonomous limited only to opportunist and
reformist “workers” organisations, or does it threaten any
organisation, including one with a revolutionary program and a
revolutionary practice? Is not a developing bureaucracy the unavoidable
consequence of any division of labour, including that
between “leadership” and “membership,” and even in a
revolutionary group? And is not, therefore, every revolutionary
organisation, once it has spread beyond a small milieu,
condemned at a certain point in its development and in the
development of mass struggles to become a brake on the struggle
of the proletarian masses for emancipation?
If this line of argument were
accepted as correct, it could lead to only one conclusion: that
the socialist emancipation of the working class and of humanity
is impossible – because the supposedly inevitable
“autonomisation” and degeneration of any organisation must
be seen as one part of a dilemma, the other part of
which is represented by the tendency for all unorganised
workers, all intellectuals only partially involved in action,
and all persons caught up in universal commodity production to
sink into a petty-bourgeois “false consciousness.” Only a
comprehensive, revolutionary practice, aiming at total
consciousness and enriching theory, makes it possible to avoid
the penetration of the “ideology of the ruling class” into
even the ranks of individual revolutionaries. This can only be a
collective and organised practice. If the above argument were
correct, one would have to conclude that, with or without an
organisation, advanced workers would be condemned either not to
reach political class consciousness or to rapidly lose it.
In reality, this line of
argument is false since it equates the beginning of a process
with its end result. Thus, from the existence of a danger
that even revolutionary organisations will become autonomous, it
deduces, in a static and fatalistic fashion, that this autonomy
is inevitable. This is neither empirically nor
theoretically demonstrable. For the extent of the danger of
bureaucratic degeneration of a revolutionary vanguard
organisation – and even more of a revolutionary party –
depends not only on the tendency toward autonomy, which
in fact afflicts all institutions in bourgeois society, but also
upon existing counter-tendencies. Among these are the
integration of the revolutionary organisation into an
international movement which is independent of “national”
organisations and which constantly keeps a theoretical eye on
them (not through an apparatus but through political criticism);
a close involvement in the actual class struggle and actual
revolutionary struggles that make possible a continuous
selection of cadres in practice; a systematic attempt to do away
with the division of labour by ensuring a continuous rotation of
personnel between factory, university and full-time party
functionaries; institutional guarantees (limitations on the
income of full-timers, defence of the organisational norms of
internal democracy and the freedom to form tendencies and
factions, etc.).
The outcome of these
contradictory tendencies depends on the struggle between
them, which, in turn, is ultimately determined by two
social factors [47]:
on the one hand, the degree of special social interest
set loose by the “autonomous organisation,” and on the other
hand, the extent of the political activity of the
vanguard of the working class. Only when the latter decisively
diminishes can the former decisively break out into the open.
Thus, the entire argument amounts to a tedious tautology: During
a period of increasing passivity the working class
cannot be actively struggling for its liberation. It does not at
all prove that during a period of increasing activity
on the part of advanced workers, revolutionary organisations are
not an effective instrument for bringing about liberation,
though their “arbitrariness” can and must be circumscribed
by the independent activity of the class (or of its advanced
sections). The revolutionary organisation is an instrument for
making revolutions. And, without the increasing political
activity of broad masses of workers, proletarian revolutions are
simply not possible.
VI. Organisational theory,
democratic centralism and soviet democracy
The objection was made to
Lenin’s theory of organisation that through its exaggerated
centralisation it would prevent the development of internal
party democracy. But this objection is a confused one, for
inasmuch as the Leninist principles of organisation restrict the
organisation to active members operating under a collective
control, they actually expand rather than reduce the scope
of party democracy.
Once a workers organisation
surpasses a certain numerical size there are basically only two
possible organisational models: that of the dues-paying
electoral club (or territorial organisation), which corresponds
today to the organisational forms of the Social-Democratic Party
of Germany and of the French Communist Party; or that of a
combat unit based on the selection of only active and conscious
members. To be sure, the first model in theory permits a certain
latitude for grumblers and opponents to fool around in, but only
where matters of secondary importance are involved. Otherwise,
the great mass of the apolitical and passive membership provides
the apparatus with a voting base that can always be mobilized,
and which has nothing to do with class consciousness. (A not
insignificant number of these members are even materially
dependent on the apparatus – the bulk of the municipal and
administrative workers and employees, the employees of the
workers organisation itself, etc.) In the combat organisation,
however, which is composed of members that have to exhibit a
minimum of consciousness simply to become members, the
possibility of finding independent thinking is actually much
greater. Neither “pure apparatchiks” nor pure careerists can
take over as easily as in an ordinary electoral club. So
differences of opinion will be resolved less in terms of
material dependency or abstract “loyalty” than according to
actual substance. To be sure, the mere fact that the
organisation is composed in this fashion is no automatic
guarantee against bureaucratisation of the organisation. But at
least it provides an essential condition for preventing it. [48]
The relation between the revolutionary organisation (a party
nucleus or a party) and the mass of workers abruptly changes as
soon as an actual revolutionary explosion occurs. At that point
the seeds sown over the years by revolutionary and consciously
socialist elements start sprouting. Broad masses are able to
achieve revolutionary class consciousness at once. The
revolutionary initiatives of broad masses can far outdistance
that of many revolutionary groupings.
In his History of the
Russian Revolution, Trotsky emphasised in several
instances that at certain conjunctures in the revolution the
Russian working masses were even ahead of the Bolshevik Party. [49]
Nevertheless, one should not generalise from this fact, and
above all, it must not be separated from the fact that, prior to
Lenin’s April Theses, the Bolshevik Party’s
strategic conception of the nature and goal of the Russian
revolution was insufficiently worked out. [50]
It ran the risk of having to pay for this until Lenin took
decisive action with his April Theses. He was
able to do so with such ease, however, because the masses if
educated worker-Bolsheviks were pushing him in that very
direction and were themselves a refection of the powerful
radicalisation of the Russian working class.
An objective, i.e.,
comprehensive, view of the role of the Bolshevik Party
organisation in the Russian revolution would no doubt have to be
formulated somewhat differently. While the leading cadre of the
party proved several times to be a conservative block preventing
the party from going over to Trotsky’s position on the
struggle for the dictatorship of the proletariat (soviet power),
at the same time it became evident that the crystallisation of a
revolutionary workers cadre schooled in two decades of
revolutionary organisation and revolutionary activity was
instrumental in making this decisive strategic turn a success.
Should one wish to construct a correlation between the Stalinist
bureaucracy and the “Leninist concept of the party,” one
would at least have to make allowances for this decisive element
of intervention. Stalin’s victory was not the result of
the Leninist Theory of organisation – but the result of the
disappearance of a decisive component of this concept: the
presence of a broad layer of worker cadres, schooled in
revolution and maintaining a high degree of activity, with a
close relationship to the masses. Moreover, Lenin himself
would have in no way denied that in the absence of this factor
the Leninist concept of the party could turn into its opposite. [51]
The soviet system is the only
universal answer discovered thus far by the working class to the
question of how to organise its independent activity during and
following the revolution. [52]
It allows all of the forces within the class – and all the
labouring and progressive layers of society in general – to be
brought together in a simultaneous, open confrontation between
the various tendencies existing within the class itself. Every
true soviet system – i.e., one that is actually elected by the
mass of the workers and has not been imposed upon them by one or
another selective power apparatus – will for that reason only
be able to reject the social and ideological diversity of the
proletarian layers emphasised above. A workers council is in
reality a united front of the most diverse political tendencies
that are in agreement on one central point: the common defence
of the revolution against the class enemy. (In the same way, a
strike committee reflects the most widely differing tendencies
among the workers, yet with one exception: It includes only
those tendencies that are participating in the strike. Scabs
have no place in a strike committee.)
There is no contradiction
whatever between the existence of a revolutionary organisation
of the Leninist type and genuine soviet democracy, or soviet
power. On the contrary, without the systematic organisational
work of a revolutionary vanguard, a soviet system will either be
quickly throttled by reformist and semi-reformist bureaucracies
(cf. the German soviet system from 1918 to 1919), or it loses
its political effectiveness due to its inability to solve the
central political tasks (cf. the Spanish revolutionary
committees between July 1936 and spring 1937).
The hypothesis that a soviet
system makes parties superfluous has one of two sources. Either
it proceeds from the naive assumption that the introduction of
soviets homogenises the working class overnight, dissolves all
differences of ideology and interest, and automatically and
spontaneously suggests to the entire working class “the
revolutionary solution” to all the strategic and
tactical problems of the revolution. Or, it is merely a pretext
for giving to a small group of self-appointed “leaders” the
opportunity to manipulate a rather broad, inarticulate mass in
that this mass is deprived of any possibility of systematically
coming to grips with these strategic and tactical questions of
the revolution, i.e., of freely discussing and politically
differentiating itself. (This is obviously the case, for
example, with the Yugoslav system of so-called self-management.)
The revolutionary organisation can,
therefore, guarantee the working masses in the soviet system a
greater degree of independent activity and self-awareness, and
thereby of revolutionary class consciousness, than could an
undifferentiated system of representation. But of course to this
end it must stimulate and not hold back the independent action
of the working masses. It is precisely this independent
initiative of the masses which reaches its fullest development
in the soviet system. Again we reach a similar conclusion: The
Leninist concept of organisation, built upon a correct
revolutionary strategy (i.e., on a correct assessment of the
objective historical process), is simply the collective
co-ordinator of the activity of the masses, the collective
memory and digested experience of the masses, in place of a
constantly repetitive and expanding discontinuity in time, space
and consciousness.
History has also shown in this
connection that there is a substantial difference between a
party calling itself a revolutionary and actually being
a revolutionary party. When a group of functionaries not only
opposes the initiative and activity of the masses but seeks to
frustrate them by any means, including military force (one
thinks of Hungary in October-November 1956 or Czechoslovakia
since August 1968), when this group not only finds no common
language with a soviet system springing spontaneously from mass
struggles, but throttles and destroys this system behind a
pretext of defending “the leading role of the party” [53]
– then we are obviously no longer dealing with a revolutionary
party of the proletariat but with an apparatus that represents
the special interests of a privileged layer deeply hostile to
the independent activity of the masses: the bureaucracy. The
fact that a revolutionary party can degenerate into a party of
bureaucracy is, however, no more an argument against the
Leninist concept of organisation than the fact that doctors have
killed, not cured, many patients represents an argument against
medical science. Any step away from this concept toward
“pure” mass spontaneity would be comparable to reverting
from medical science to quackery.
VII. Sociology of economism,
bureaucratism and spontaneity
When we emphasised that
Lenin’s concept of organisation in reality represents a
concept of the current potential for proletarian revolution, we
already touched upon the central factor in the Leninist theory
of proletarian, class consciousness: the problem of the
definition of the revolutionary subject under capitalism. For
Marx and Lenin (as well as for Luxemburg and Trotsky, although
they did not draw all the necessary conclusions from this fact
until some time before 1914), the revolutionary subject is the
only potentially, only periodically revolutionary working class
as it works, thinks and lives under capitalism, i.e., in the
totality of its social existence. [54]
The Leninist theory of organisation proceeds directly from this
assessment of the position of the revolutionary subject, for it
is self-evident that a subject, thus defined, can only be a contradictory
one. On the one hand it is exposed to wage slavery, alienated
labour, the reification of all human relations, and the
influence of bourgeois and petty-bourgeois ideology. On the
other hand, at periodic intervals it passes over into a
radicalising class struggle, and even into open revolutionary
battle against the capitalist mode of production and the
bourgeois state apparatus. It is in this periodic fluctuation
that the history of the real class struggle of the last
one hundred and fifty years is expressed. It is absolutely
impossible to sum up the history of, say, the French or the
German labour movements of the past hundred years with either
the formula “increasing passivity” or “uninterrupted
revolutionary activity.” It is obviously a unity of both
elements with an alternating emphasis on one or the other.
As ideological tendencies,
opportunism and sectarianism have their deepest theoretical,
roots in an undialectical definition of the revolutionary
subject. For the opportunists, this revolutionary subject is the
everyday worker. They tend to imitate the attitude of
this worker in everything and “to idolise his backward
side,” as Plekhanov so well put it. If the workers are
concerned only with questions limited to the shops, then they
are “pure trade unionists.” If the workers are caught up in
a wave of patriotic jingoism, then they become social-patriots
or social-imperialists. If the workers submit to cold-war
propaganda, they become cold-warriors: “The masses are always
right.” The latest and the most wretched expression of such
opportunism consists of determining the program – let it be an
electoral program – no longer through an objective scientific
analysis of society but with the aid of ... opinion polls.
But this opportunism leads to
an insoluble contradiction. Fortunately, the moods of the masses
do not stand still but can change dramatically in a rather short
period of time. Today the workers are concerned only with
internal shop questions, but tomorrow they will throng the
streets in a political demonstration. Today they are “for”
the defence of the imperialist fatherland against the
“external enemy,” but tomorrow they will be fed up with the
war and again recognise their own ruling class as the main
enemy. Today they passively accept collaboration with the
bosses, but tomorrow they will move against it through a wildcat
strike. The logic of opportunism leads – once the adaptation
to bourgeois society has been excused through references to the
attitude of the “masses” – to resistance to these very
masses as soon as they begin in a sudden reversal, to move
into action against bourgeois society.
Sectarians simplify the
revolutionary subject just as much as opportunists, but in the
opposite sense. If only the everyday worker counts for the
opportunists – i.e., the worker who is assimilating and
adapting to bourgeois relations – for the sectarians it is
only the “ideal” proletarian, one who acts like a
revolutionary, who counts. If the worker does not behave in a
revolutionary fashion, he has ceased to be a revolutionary
subject: he is demoted to being “bourgeois.” Extreme
sectarians – such as certain ultraleft “spontaneists,”
certain Stalinists, and certain Maoists – will even go so far
as to equate the working class with the capitalist class
if it hesitates to completely accept the particular sectarian
ideology in question. [55]
Extreme objectivism on the one
hand (“everything the workers do is revolutionary”), and
extreme subjectivity on the other hand (“only those who accept
our doctrine are revolutionary or proletarian”), join hands in
the final analysis when they deny the objectively revolutionary
character of huge mass struggles led by masses with a
contradictory consciousness. For the opportunist objectivists
these struggles are not revolutionary because “next month the
majority will still go ahead and vote for the SPD (West German
Social Democrats) or DeGaulle.” For the sectarian
subjectivists they have nothing to do with revolution “because
the (i.e., our) revolutionary group is still too weak.”
The social nature of these two
tendencies can be ascertained without difficulty. It corresponds
to the petty-bourgeois intelligentsia: The opportunists for the
most part represent the intelligentsia tied to the labour
bureaucracy in mass organisations or in the bourgeois state
apparatus, while the sectarians represent an intelligentsia that
is either declassed or merely watches things from the sidelines,
remaining outside of the real movement. In both cases, the
forced separation between the objective and subjective factors
at work in the contradictory but undivided revolutionary subject
corresponds to a divorce between practice and theory which can
lead only to an opportunist practice and to an idealising
“theory” embodying “false consciousness.”
It is characteristic, however,
for many opportunists (among others, trade-union bureaucrats),
as well as many sectarian literati, to accuse precisely the
revolutionary Marxists of being petty-bourgeois intellectuals
who would like to “subjugate” the working class. [56]
This question also plays a certain role in the discussions
within the revolutionary student movement. Therefore, it is
necessary to analyse more closely the problem of the sociology
of the bureaucracy, of economism, and of spontaneity (or, of the
“handicraftsman’s approach” to the question of
organisation).
The mediation between manual
and mental labour, production and accumulation, occurs at
several points in bourgeois society, though at different levels,
for example, in the factory. What is meant by the general
concept of “intelligentsia.” or “intellectual petty
bourgeoisie” or “technical intelligentsia” corresponds in
reality to many diverse activities of such mediation whose
relation to the actual class struggle is quite distinct. One
could essentially distinguish the following categories (which in
no way do we claim constitute a complete analysis):
- The genuine intermediaries
between capital and labour in the process of production,
i.e., the secondary officers of capital: foremen,
timekeepers and other cadre personnel in the factories,
among whose tasks is the maintenance, in the interest of
capital, of labour discipline within the factory.
- The intermediaries between
science and technique, or between technique and production:
laboratory assistants, scientific researchers, inventors,
technologists, planners, project engineers, draftsmen, etc.
In contrast to category 1, these layers are not accomplices
in the process of extracting surplus value from the
producer. They take part in the material process of
production itself and. for that reason are not exploiters
but producers of surplus value.
- The intermediaries between
production and realisation of surplus value: advertising
managers and offices, market research institutes, cadres and
scientists occupied in the distribution sector, marketing
specialists, etc.
- The intermediaries between
buyers and sellers of the commodity labour power: Above all,
these are the trade union functionaries and, in a wider
sense, all functionaries of the bureaucratised mass
organisations of the labour movement.
- The intermediaries between
capital and labour in the sphere of the superstructure, the
ideological producers (i.e., those who are occupied with
producing ideology): a section of the bourgeois politicians
(“public opinion makers”), the bourgeois professors of
the so-called humanities, journalists, some artists, etc.
- The intermediaries between
science and the working class, the theoretical producers,
who have not been professionally incorporated into the
ideological production of the ruling class and are
relatively able, being free from material dependency on this
production, to engage in criticism of bourgeois relations.
One could add a seventh group,
which is partially included in the fifth, and partially in the
sixth, In classical, stable bourgeois society, teaching as a
profession falls into category 5, both because of the unlimited
predominance of bourgeois ideology and because of the generally
abstract and ideological character of all professional teaching.
With the growing structural crisis in the neocapitalist high
schools and universities, however, a change in its objective
standards takes place. On the one hand, the general crisis of
capitalism precipitates a general crisis in neocapitalist
ideology, which is increasingly called into question. On the
other hand, teaching serves less as abstract, ideological
indoctrination and more as the direct technocratic preparation
for the future intellectual workers (of categories 2 and 3) to
be incorporated into the process of production. This makes it
possible for the content of such teaching to be increasingly
tied to a regained awareness of individual alienation, as well
as to social criticism in related fields (and even to social
criticism in general).
It now becomes clear which part
of the intelligentsia will exert a negative influence upon the
developing class consciousness of the proletariat: It is above
all groups 3, 4 and 5. (We need say nothing about group 1
because in general it keeps its distance from the workers
organisations anyway.) What is most dangerous for the initiative
and self-assurance of the working class is a symbiosis or fusion
of groups 4 and 5, as has occurred on a broad scale since the
first world war in the social-democratic and today already
partially in the Moscow-oriented Communist mass organisations in
the West.
Groups 2 and 6, on the other
hand, can only enhance the impact of the working-class and
revolutionary organisations because they equip them with the
knowledge that is indispensable for a relentless critique of
bourgeois society and for the successful overthrow of this
society, and even more for the successful taking over of the
means of production by the associated producers.
Those who rail against the
growing union of workers organisations with groups 2 and 6 of
the intelligentsia objectively assist groups 3, 4 and 5 in
exerting their negative influence on the working class. For
never in history has there been a class struggle that has not
been accompanied by an ideological struggle. [57]
It boils down to a question of determining which
ideology can sink roots in the working class; or, to phrase it
better, whether bourgeois and petty-bourgeois ideology or
Marxist scientific theory will develop among the workers.
Whoever opposes “every outside intellectual influence”
within the working class in struggle either forgets or pushes
aside the fact that the influence which groups 1, 3, 4 and 5
exert on this working class is permanently and unremittingly
at work upon the proletariat through the entire mechanism of
bourgeois society and capitalist economy, and that the ultraleft
“spontaneists” have no panacea at their disposal for putting
an end to this process. To thunder against the influence of
Marxist intellectuals within the working class means simply to
allow the influence of the bourgeois intelligentsia to spread
without opposition. [58]
Still worse: By resisting the formation of a revolutionary
organisation and the education of professional proletarian
revolutionaries, Mensheviks and “spontaneists” are
objectively forced to help perpetuate the division between
manual and intellectual labour, i.e., the spiritual subjugation
of the workers to the intellectuals and the rather rapid
bureaucratisation of the workers organisations. For, a worker
who continuously remains within the capitalist process of
production will most often not be in a position to globally
assimilate theory, and will thereby remain dependent upon
“petty-bourgeois specialists.” For that reason, a decisive
step can be, taken within the revolutionary organisation toward
the intellectual emancipation of at least the most advanced
workers and toward an initial victory over the division of
labour within the workers movement itself through the
intermittent removal of workers from the factories.
This is not yet the final word
on the sociology of spontaneism. We must ask ourselves: In which
layers of the working class will the “antipathy” and
“distrust” toward intellectuals have the most influence?
Obviously in those layers whose social and economic existence most
sharply exposes them to an actual conflict with intellectual
labour. By and large, these are the workers of the small
and medium-sized factories threatened by technological progress;
self-taught workers who, through personal effort, have
differentiated themselves from the mass; workers who have
scrambled to the top of bureaucratic organisations; workers who,
because of their low educational and cultural level, are the
furthest removed from intellectual labour – and therefore also
regard it with the greatest mistrust and hostility. In other
words, the social basis of economist, spontaneity, the
“handicraftsman’s approach” to the question of
organisation and hostility toward science within the working
class is the craft layer of this class.
On the other hand, among the
workers of the large factories and cities, of the extensive
branches of industry in the forefront of technological progress,
the thirst for knowledge, the greater familiarity with technical
and scientific processes, and the greater audacity in projecting
the conquest of power in both the factory and the state make it
much easier to understand the objectively necessary role of
revolutionary theoreticians and of the revolutionary
organisation.
The spontaneous tendencies in
the labour movement often, if not always, correspond exactly to
this social basis. This was especially true for
anarcho-syndicalism in the Latin countries before the first
world war. This was also true for Menshevism, which was
thoroughly defeated by Bolshevism in the large metropolitan
factories, but which found its most important proletarian base
in the typically small-town mining and oil-field districts of
southern Russia. [59]
Attempts today, in the era of the third industrial revolution,
to revive this craftsman caste approach under the pretext of
guaranteeing “workers autonomy” could only have the same
result as in the past – namely, to dissipate the forces of the
advanced and potentially revolutionary working class and to give
a boost to the semi-craft, bureaucratised sections of the
movement that are under the constant influence of bourgeois
ideology.
VIII. Scientific
intelligentsia, social science and proletarian class
consciousness
The massive reintroduction of
intellectual labour into the process of production brought about
by the third industrial revolution, which was foreseen by Marx
and whose foundations were already laid in the second industrial
revolution [60], has
created the prerequisite for a much broader layer of the
scientific intelligentsia to regain the awareness of alienation
which it had lost through its removal from the process of direct
production of surplus value and its transformation into a direct
or indirect consumer of surplus value. For it, too, is overcome
by alienation in bourgeois society. This is the material basis
not only for the student revolt in the imperialist countries but
also for the possibility of involving increasing numbers of
scientists and technicians into the revolutionary movement.
The participation of the
intelligentsia in the classical socialist movement before the
first world war generally tended to decline. Though it was
considerable at the start of the movement, it became smaller and
smaller as the organised mass movement of the working class
became stronger. In a little known polemic against Max Adler in
1910, Trotsky revealed the causes of this process to be on the
whole materialistic: the intelligentsia’s social dependency on
the big bourgeoisie and the bourgeois state; an ideological
identification with the class interests it thereby serves; and
the inability of the workers movement, organised as a
“counter-society,” to compete with its counterpart. Trotsky
predicted that this would probably change very quickly, in a
revolutionary epoch, on the eve of the proletarian revolution. [61]
From these correct premises,
however, he drew what were already incorrect tactical
conclusions, when for instance he failed to see the great
importance which in 1908-1909 Lenin accorded the student
movement (which was re-emerging in the middle of the victorious
counter-revolution), considering it an albatross for the
subsequent, new rise in the revolutionary mass movement (that
was to begin in 1912).
He even went so far as to
maintain that it was the “fault” of the leading
revolutionary intelligentsia in the Russian Social Democracy if
it was able to spread “its overall social characteristics: a
spirit of sectarianism, an individualism typical of
intellectuals, and ideological fetishism.” [62]
As Trotsky later admitted, he at that time under-estimated the political
and social significance of the faction fight between the
Bolsheviks and the Liquidators, which was only an extension of
the earlier struggle between Bolsheviks and Mensheviks. History
was to show that this struggle had nothing to do with a product
of “intellectual sectarianism,” but with the separation of
socialist, revolutionary consciousness from petty-bourgeois,
reformist consciousness. [63]
It is correct, however, that
the participation of the Russian revolutionary intelligentsia in
the building of the revolutionary class party of the Russian
proletariat was still a pure product of individual selection
without any social roots. And since the October revolution, this
has inevitably turned against the proletarian
revolution, for the masses of the technical intelligentsia were
not able to go over to the camp of the revolution. At
first they sabotaged economic production and the methods of
social organisation on the broadest scale; then their
co-operation had to be “bought” through high salaries; and
finally they were transformed into the driving force behind the
bureaucratisation and degeneration of this revolution. Inasmuch
as the position of the technical intelligentsia (especially
category 2 above) in the material process of production has
today decisively changed, and since this technical
intelligentsia is gradually being transformed into a section of
the wage-earning class, the possibility of its massive
participation in the revolutionary process and in the
reorganisation of society stands on much firmer ground than in
the past. Frederick Engels had already, pointed to the
historically decisive role this intelligentsia could play in the
construction of the socialist society.
“In order to take over and
put into operation the means of production, we need people, and
in large numbers, who are technically trained. We do not have
them, ... I foresee us in the next eight to ten years recruiting
enough young technicians, doctors, lawyers and teachers to be in
a position to let party comrades administer the factories and
essential goods for the nation. Then our accession to power will
be quite natural and will work itself out relatively smoothly.
If, on the other hand, we prematurely come to power through a
war, the technicians will be our main opponents, and will
deceive and betray us whenever possible. We will have to use
terror against them and still they will shit all over us.” [64]
Of course, it must be added
that in the course of this third industrial revolution the
working class itself, which is much better qualified than in
1890, exhibits a much greater ability to directly manage the
factories than in Engels’ time. But in the final analysis, it
is technical abilities that are required for the broad masses to
be able to exert political and social control over the
“specialists” (a matter about which Lenin had so many
illusions in 1918). A growing union between the technical
intelligentsia and the industrial proletariat, and the growing
participation of revolutionary intellectuals in the
revolutionary party, can only facilitate that control.
As the contradiction between
the objective socialisation of production and labour on the one
hand, and private appropriation on the other, intensifies (i.e.,
as the crisis of the capitalist relations of production
sharpens) – and today we are experiencing a new and sharper
form of this contradiction, which underlay the May 1968 events
in France and the mass struggles in Italy in 1969 – and as
neo-capitalism seeks to win a new lease on life by raising the
working class’s level of consumption, science will
increasingly become for the masses a revolutionary, productive
force in two regards: With automation and the growing mountain
of commodities, it produces not only a growing crisis in the
production and distribution process of capital, which is based
upon generalised commodity production; it also produces
revolutionary consciousness in growing masses of people by
allowing the myths and masks of the capitalist routine to be
torn away, and by making it possible for the worker,
reconquering the consciousness of being alienated, to put an end
to that alienation. As the decisive barrier which today holds
back the working class from acquiring political class
consciousness is found to reside less in the misery of the
masses or the extreme narrowness of their surroundings than in
the constant influence of petty-bourgeois and bourgeois
ideological consumption and mystification, it is precisely then
that the eye-opening function of critical social science can
play a truly revolutionary role in the new awakening of the
class consciousness among the masses. Of course, this makes
necessary the existence of concrete ties with the working masses
– a requirement that can only be met by the advanced workers
on the one hand and the revolutionary organisation on the other.
And this also requires the revolutionary, scientific
intelligentsia not to “go to the people” with the modest
populist masochism that restricts it to humbly supporting
struggles for higher wages but to bring the awakened and
critical layers of the working class what they are unable to
achieve by themselves, due to their fragmented state of
consciousness: the scientist knowledge and awareness that will
make it possible for them to recognise the scandal of concealed
exploitation and disguised oppression for what it is.
IX. Historical pedagogy and
communication of class consciousness
Once it is understood that the
Leninist theory of organisation tries to answer the problems of
the current potential for revolution and of the revolutionary
subject, this theory then leads directly to the question of
historical pedagogy, i.e., the problem of transforming
potential class consciousness into actual class consciousness,
and trade-unionist consciousness into political, revolutionary
consciousness. This problem can only be resolved in the light of
the classification of the working class delineated as above –
into the mass of the workers, advanced workers, and organised
revolutionary cadre.
To assimilate its growing class
consciousness, each layer requires its own methods of
instruction, goes through its own learning process and needs to
have a special form of communication with the class as a whole
and with the realm of theoretical production. The historical
role of the revolutionary vanguard party Lenin had in mind can
be summed up as that of jointly expressing these three forms of
pedagogy.
The broad masses learn only
through action. To hope to “impart” to them revolutionary
consciousness through propaganda is an endeavour worthy of
Sisyphus – and as fruitless. Yet although the masses learn
only through action, all actions do not necessarily lead to a
mass acquisition of revolutionary class consciousness.
Actions around immediately realisable economic and political
goals that can be completely achieved within the framework of
the capitalist social order do not produce revolutionary class
consciousness. This was one of the great illusions of the
“optimistic” Social Democrats at the end of the nineteenth
century and the beginning of the twentieth (including Engels)
who believed that there was a straight line leading from partial
successes in electoral struggles and strikes to revolutionary
consciousness and to an increase in the proletariat’s
revolutionary combatively. [65]
This has proven to be
historically incorrect. These partial successes certainly played
a significant and positive role in strengthening the
self-confidence and combatively of the proletarian massed in
general. (The anarchists were wrong to reject these partial
struggles out of hand.) Yet they did not prepare the working
masses for revolutionary struggle. The German working class’
lack of experience in revolutionary struggles on the one hand,
and the existence, on the other hand, of such experience in the
Russian working class, was the most important difference in
consciousness between the two classes on the eve of the first
world war. It decisively contributed to the dissimilar outcome
of the revolutions of 1917-1919 in Germany and in Russia.
Since the goal of mass actions
is generally the satisfaction of immediate needs, it becomes an
important aspect of revolutionary strategy to link to these
needs demands that objectively cannot be achieved or co-opted
within the framework of the capitalist social order, and which
produce an objectively revolutionary dynamic that has to lead to
a test of strength between the two decisive social classes over
the question of power. This is the strategy of transitional
demands which, through the efforts of Lenin, was incorporated
into the program of the Communist International at its fourth
congress, and which was later elaborated by Trotsky into the
main body of the program of the Fourth International. [66]
The development of
revolutionary class consciousness among the broad masses is
possible only if they accumulate experiences of struggles
that are not only limited to the winning of partial demands
within the framework of capitalism. The gradual injection of
these demands into mass struggles can come about only through
the efforts of a broad layer of advanced workers who are closely
linked to the masses and who disseminate and publicise these
demands (which normally do not spontaneously grow out of the
day-to-day experiences of the class) in the factories,
experimenting with them in various skirmishes, and spreading
them through agitation, until a point is reached where
favourable objective and subjective conditions converge, making
the realisation of these demands the actual objective of great
strikes, demonstrations, agitational campaigns, etc.
Although revolutionary class
consciousness among the broad masses develops only out of the
experience of objectively revolutionary struggle, among
advanced workers it flows from the experience of life, work and
struggle in general. These experiences do not necessarily need
to be revolutionary at all. From the daily experiences of class
conflict, these advanced workers draw the elementary conclusions
about the need for class solidarity, class action and class
organisation. The programmatic and organisational forms through
which this action and organisation are to be led will differ
greatly depending upon objective conditions and concrete
experiences. But the advanced workers’ experience of life,
work and struggle leads them to the threshold of understanding
the inadequacy of activity which seeks merely to reform the
existing society rather than abolish it.
The activity of the
revolutionary vanguard can make it possible for the class
consciousness of the advanced workers to cross over this
threshold. It can fulfil this role of catalyst neither
automatically nor without regard for objective conditions. It
can only fulfil it when it is itself equal to the task, i.e., if
the content of ifs theoretical, propagandistic and literary
activity corresponds to the needs of the advanced workers, and
if the form of this activity does not trample underfoot the laws
of pedagogy (avoiding ultimatistic formulations). At the same
time, this kind of activity must be linked to activity of a
practical nature and to a political perspective,
thus enhancing the credibility of both the revolutionary
strategy and the organisation putting it forward.
In periods of abating class
struggles, of a temporary decline in the self-confidence of the
working class, during which the stability of the class enemy
appears temporarily assured, the revolutionary vanguard will not
be able to achieve its objective even if its activity is
completely equal to the task of catalysing revolutionary class
consciousness among the broadest layer of advanced workers. The
belief that a mere defence of “the correct tactic” or “the
correct line” is sufficient to miraculously generate a growing
revolutionary force, even in periods of declining class
struggle, is an illusion stemming from bourgeois rationalism,
not from the materialist dialectic. This illusion, incidentally,
is the cause of most splits within the revolutionary movement
because the organisational sectarianism of the splitters is
based on the naive view that the “application of the correct
tactic” can win over more people in the as yet untouched
periphery than it can among revolutionaries who are already
organised. As long as the objective conditions remain
unfavourable, these splits for that reason usually result in
grouplets that are even weaker than those whose “false
tactics” made them seem so worthy of condemnation in the first
place.
This does not mean, however,
that the work of the revolutionary vanguard among the advanced
workers remains useless or ineffectual during unfavourable
objective circumstances. It produces no great immediate
successes, yet it is a tremendously important, and even
decisive, preparation for that turning point when class
struggles once again begin to mount!
For just as broad masses with
no experience of revolutionary struggle cannot develop
revolutionary class consciousness, advanced workers who have
never heard of transitional demands cannot introduce them into
the next wave of class struggle. The patient, persistent
preparation carried out, with constant attention to detail, by
the revolutionary vanguard organisation, sometimes over a period
of years, pays off in rich dividends the day the “natural
leaders of the class” still hesitating and not yet completely
free from hostile influences, suddenly, during a big strike or
demonstration, take up the demand for workers control and thrust
it to the forefront of the struggle. [67]
To be in a position, however,
to convince a country’s advanced workers and radical
intelligentsia of the need to extend broad mass struggles beyond
the level of immediate demands to that of transitional demands,
it is not enough for the revolutionary vanguard organisation to
learn by heart a list of such demands culled from Lenin and
Trotsky. It must acquire a twofold knowledge and a two-sided
method of learning. On the one hand, it must assimilate the body
of the experiences of the international proletariat over more
than a century of revolutionary class struggle. On the other
hand, it must carry on a continuous, serious analysis of the
present overall social reality, national as well as
international. This alone makes it possible to apply the lessons
of history to the reality at hand. It is clear that on the basis
of the Marxist theory of knowledge, only practice can ultimately
provide the criterion for measuring the actual theoretical
assimilation of present-day reality. For that reason,
international practice is an absolute prerequisite for a Marxist
international analysis, and an international organisation is an
absolute prerequisite for such a practice.
Without a serious assimilation
of the entire historical experience of the international workers
movement from the revolution of 1848 to the present, it is
impossible to determine with scientific precision either the
contradictions of present neocapitalist society – on a world
scale as well as in individual countries – or the concrete
contradiction accompanying the formation of proletarian class
consciousness, or the kind of struggles that could lead to a
pre-revolutionary situation. History is the only laboratory for
the social sciences. Without assimilating the lessons of
history, a pseudo-revolutionary Marxist today would be no betted
than a “medical student” who refused to set foot inside the
dissecting laboratory.
It should be pointed out in
this connection that all attempts to keep the newly emerging
revolutionary movement “aloof from the splits of the past”
demonstrate a complete failure to understand the socio-political
nature of this differentiation within the international workers
movement. If one puts aside the inevitable personal and
incidental factors involved in these differentiations, one has
to come to the conclusion that the great disputes in the
international workers movement since the foundation of the First
International (the disputes between Marxism and anarchism;
between Marxism and revisionism; between Bolshevism and
Menshevism; between internationalism and social-patriotism;
between defenders of the dictatorship of the proletariat and
defenders of bourgeois democracy; between Trotskyism and
Stalinism; between Maoism and Khrushchevism) touch upon
fundamental questions relating to the proletarian revolution and
to the strategy and tactics of revolutionary class struggle. These
basic questions are products of the very nature of capitalism,
the proletariat and revolutionary struggle. They will
therefore remain pressing questions as long as the problem of
creating a classless society on a world scale has not been
solved in practical terms. No “tactfulness,” no matter how
artful, and no “conciliationism,” no matter how magnanimous,
can in the long run prevent these questions from rising out of
practice itself to confront each new generation of
revolutionaries. All that is accomplished by attempting to avoid
a discussion of these problems is that instead of raising,
analysing and solving them in a methodical and scientific
fashion, this is done unsystematically, at random, without plan,
and without sufficient training and knowledge.
However, while the assimilation
of the historical substance of Marxist theory is necessary, it
is nevertheless in and of itself an insufficient prerequisite
for conveying revolutionary class consciousness to the advanced
workers and the radical intelligentsia. In addition, a
systematic analysis of the present is required without which
theory cannot furnish the means for disclosing either the
immediate capacity of the working class for struggle or the
“weak links” in the neo-capitalist mode of production and
bourgeois society; nor can it furnish the means for formulating
the appropriate transitional demands (as well as the proper
pedagogical approach to raising them). Only the combination of a
serious, complete social and critical analysis of the present
and the assimilation of the lessons of the history of the
workers movement can create an effective instrument for the
theoretical accomplishment of the task of a revolutionary
vanguard. [68]
Without the experience of
revolutionary struggle by broad masses, there can be no
revolutionary class consciousness among these masses. Without
the conscious intervention of advanced workers, who inject
transitional demands into workers struggles, there can hardly be
experiences of revolutionary struggle on the part of the broad
masses. Without the spreading of transitional demands by a
revolutionary vanguard, there can be no possibility of advanced
workers influencing mass struggles, in a truly anti-capitalist
sense. Without a revolutionary program, without a thorough study
of the history of the revolutionary workers movement, without an
application of this study to the present, and without practical
proof of the ability of the revolutionary vanguard to
successfully play a leading role in at least a few sectors and
situations, there can be no possibility of convincing the
advanced workers of the need for the revolutionary organisation
and therefore no possibility (or only an unlikely one) that the
appropriate transitional demands for the objective situation can
be worked out by the advanced workers. In this way the various
factors in the formation of class consciousness intertwine and
underpin the timeliness of the Leninist conception of
organisation.
The process of building a
revolutionary party acquires its unified character through
jointly expressing the learning of the masses in action, the
learning of the advanced workers in practical experience, and
the learning of the revolutionary cadre in the transmission of
revolutionary theory and practice. There is a constant
interrelationship between learning and teaching, even among the
revolutionary cadre, who have to achieve the ability to shed any
arrogance resulting from their theoretical knowledge. This
ability proceeds from the understanding that theory proves its
right to exist only through its connection to the real class
struggle and by its capacity to transform potentially
revolutionary class consciousness into the actual revolutionary
class consciousness of broad layers of workers. The famous
observation by Marx that the educators must themselves be
educated [69] means
exactly what it says. It does not mean that a consciously
revolutionary transformation of society is possible without a
revolutionary pedagogy. And it is given a more complete
expression in the Marxist proposition that “In revolutionary
activity the changing of oneself coincides with the changing of
circumstances.” [70]
Footnotes
1.
This concept was by no means invented by Lenin but corresponds
to a tradition leading from Engels, through Kautsky, to the
classical doctrines of the international Social Democracy
between 1880 and 1905. The Hainfeld Program of
the Austrian Social Democracy, drafted in 1888-1889, explicitly
states: “Socialist consciousness is something that is brought
into the proletarian class struggle from outside, not something
that organically develops out of the class struggle.” In 1901,
Kautsky published his article Akademiker und Proletarier
in Neue Zeit (19th year, Vol.2, April 17. 1901)
in which the same thought is expressed (p.89) in a form that
directly inspired Lenin’s What is to Be Done?
It is well known that Marx had
developed no uniform concept of the party. But while he
sometimes totally rejected the idea of a vanguard organisation,
he also formulated a conception which very closely approaches
that of “introducing revolutionary-socialist consciousness”
into the working class. Note the following passage from a
letter, written by him, on January 1, 1870, from the executive
board of the First International to the federal committee of
Romanic Switzerland:
“The English possess all the
necessary material prerequisites for a social
revolution. What they lack is a spirit of qeneralisation and
revolutionary passion. That the executive board alone can
remedy, and in doing so, hasten the development of a truly
revolutionary movement in this country, and hence everywhere.
“The great successes that we
have already achieved in this regard are being attested to by
the wisest and most distinguished newspapers of the ruling class
... not to mention the so-called radical members of the House of
Commons and the House of Lords, who only a short time ago had
quite a bit of innuendo on the leaders of the English workers.
They are publicly accusing us of having poisoned and almost
suffocated the English spirit of the working class, and
of having driven it to revolutionary socialism.” (Marx-Engels,
Werke, [Berlin: Dietz-Verlag, 1964], Vol.16,
pp.381-387.)
The concept of the “current
potential for revolution” in Lenin was first formulated by
Georg Lukacs, as is well known, in Geschichte und
Klassenbewusstsein and particularly in his Lenin.
2.
This is especially true for the crucial Marxian category of revolutionary
practice, which was developed in the then unknown German
Ideology.
3.
It is in this sense that, among others, the famous statement by
Marx at the beginning of The Eighteenth Brumaire of
Louis Bonaparte must be understood, in which he
stresses the constant self-critical nature of the proletarian
revolution and its tendency to come back to things that appeared
to have already been accomplished. In this connection, Marx
speaks also of the proletariat as being hypnotised by the
“undefined magnitude of its own objectives.”
4.
In the Communist Manifesto Marx and Engels
state that communists “do not set up any special principle of
their own, by which to shape and mould the proletarian
movement.” In the English edition of 1888, Engels substituted
the word “sectarian” for the word “special.” In doing
so, he expresses the fact that scientific socialism certainly
does try to advance “special” principles in the labour
movement, but only those objectively resulting from the general
course of the proletarian class struggle, i.e., from
contemporary history, and not those peculiar only to the creed
of a particular sect, i.e., to a purely incidental aspect of the
proletarian class struggle.
5.
This thought is poignantly expressed by Trotsky in the
introduction to the first Russian edition of his book, The
Permanent Revolution (New York: Merit Publishers,
1969). Mao Tse-tung too has more than once called attention to
this thought. In sharp contrast to it is the notion of a
“socialist mode of production” or even of a “developed
social system of socialism” in which the first stage of
communism is regarded as something fixed and not as simply a
transitional phase in the permanent revolutionary development
from capitalism to communism.
6.
Note Lenin’s well-known statement that there are no
“inextricable economic situations” for the imperialist
bourgeoisie.
7.
Thus the rising bourgeois class consciousness, and even the
rising plebeian or semi-proletarian class consciousness in the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, were expressed within a
completely religious framework, finding the way to overt
materialism only with the full-blown decadence of the feudal
absolutist order in the second half of the eighteenth century.
8.
Gramsci’s “concept of political and ethical hegemony,”
which an oppressed social class must establish within society
before it can take political power, expresses this possibility
especially well. Cf. Il Materialismo Storico e la
Filosofia di Benedetto Croce (Milan: Einaudi, 1964),
p.236; and also Note sul Machiavelli (Milan:
Einaudi, 1964), pp.29-37, 41-50ff. This hegemony concept has
been criticised or modified by numerous Marxist theoreticians.
See, for example, Nicos Poulantzas, Pouvoir politique et
classes sociales (Paris: Maspero, 1968), pp.210-222.
Concerning the significance of overall social consensus
with the material and moral foundations of bourgeois class rule,
see Jose Ramon Recalde, Integracion y lucha de cases en
el neo-capitalismo (Madrid: Editorial Ciencia Nueva,
1968), pp.152-157.
9.
This is expressed by Marx and Engels in the proposition in The
German Ideology that “this revolution is necessary
therefore, not only because the ruling class cannot be
overthrown in any other way, but also because the class overthrowing
it can only in a revolution succeed in ridding itself of all the
muck of ages and become fitted to found society anew.” Karl
Marx and Frederick Engels, The German Ideology
(Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1968), p.87. Cf. also the
following observation by Marx in 1850 against the Schapper
minority in the Communist League: “The minority substitutes a
dogmatic approach for a critical one, and idealism for
materialism. For it, the driving force of the revolution is mere
will power, not actual conditions. We, on the other hand, tell
the workers: ‘You will have to go through 15, 20, 50 years of
civil wars and people’s struggles not only to change the
conditions, but in order to change yourselves so you
will be capable of exercising political rule.’ You, on the
contrary, say: ‘If we can’t take power right away we might
as well go to bed.’” Karl Marx, Enthullungen über
den Kommunistenprozess zu Köln (Berlin: Buchandlung
Vorwärts, 1914), pp.52-53.
10.
Note Lenin: “Our wiseacre fails to see that it is precisely
during the revolution that we shall stand in need of the results
of our [pre-revolutionary – E.M.] theoretical battles
with the Critics in order to be able resolutely to combat their practical
positions!” What is to Be Done? (Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1964), p.163. How tragically this came true
seventeen years later in the German revolution.
11.
In this connection in What is to Be Done? Lenin
speaks of the “social-democratic” and “revolutionary”
workers in contrast to the “backward” workers.
12.
N. Bukharin, Theorie des Historischen Materialismus
(published by the Communist International: 1922), pp.343-345.
“Economic conditions had
first transformed the mass of the people of the country into
workers. The combination of capital has created for this mass a
common situation, common interests. This mass is thus already a
class as against capital, but not yet for itself. In the
struggle, of which we have noted only a few phases, this mass
becomes united, and constitutes itself as a class for itself.”
Karl Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy (New York:
International Publishers, 1963). p.173.
13.
Cf. the section of the SPD’s Erfurt Program
that was not criticised by Engels, in which the proletarians are
described as simply the class of wageworkers separated from the
means of production and condemned to sell their labor power, and
in which the class struggle is described as the objective
struggle between exploiters and exploited in modern society
(i.e., without relation to the degree of organisation or
consciousness of the wage earners). Following this objective
fact, which is established in the first four sections, comes the
following addition to the conclusion of the general body of the
program:
“The task of the
social-democratic party is to mould this struggle of the working
class into a conscious and homogeneous one and to point out what
is by nature its essential goal.” This once again explicitly
confirms that there can be classes and class struggle in
capitalist society without the struggling working class being
conscious of its class interests. Further on, in the eighth
section, the program speaks of the “class-conscious workers of
all countries,” and Engels proposes a change which again
underlines the fact that he made a definitive distinction
between the “objective” and the “subjective” concept of
class: “Instead of ‘class conscious,’ which for us is an
easily understandable abbreviation, I would say (in the
interests of general understanding and translation into foreign
languages) ‘workers permeated with the consciousness of their
class situation,’ or something like that.” Engels, Zur
Kritik des sozialdemokratischen Programmentwurfs 1891 in
Marx-Engels, Werke, Band 22 ( Berlin:
Dietz-Verlag. 1963), p.232.
14.
Lenin: “The basic prerequisite for this success [in
consolidating the party – E.M.] was, of course, the
fact that the working class, whose elite has built the Social
Democracy, differs, for objective economic reasons, from all
other classes in capitalist society in its capacity for
organisation. Without this prerequisite, the organisation of
professional revolutionaries would only be a game, an adventure
...” Lenine, Oeuvres Completes, Tome 12
(Paris: Editions Sociales, 1969), p.74.
15.
To counter this view, many critics of the Leninist concept of
organisation (beginning with Plekhanov’s article, Centralism
or Bonapartism in Iskra, No.70 [Summer
1904]), refer to a passage in The Holy Family
– The passage states: “When socialist writers ascribe this
historic role to the proletariat, it is not, as Critical
Criticism pretends to think, because they consider the
proletarians as gods. Rather the contrary. Since the
abstraction of all humanity, even of the semblance of
humanity, is practically complete in the full-grown proletariat;
since the conditions of life of the proletariat sum up all the
conditions of life of society today in all their inhuman acuity;
since man has lost himself in the proletariat, yet at the same
time has not only gained theoretical consciousness of that loss,
but through urgent, no longer disguisable, absolutely imperative
need – that practical expression of necessity
– is driven to revolt against that inhumanity; it follows that
the proletariat can and must free itself. But it cannot free
itself without abolishing the conditions of its own life. It
cannot abolish the conditions of its own life without abolishing
all the inhuman conditions of life of society today
which are summed up in its own situation. Not in vain does it go
through the stern but steeling school of labour. The
question is not what this or that proletarian, or even the whole
of the proletariat, at the moment considers as its aim.
The question is what the proletariat is and what,
consequent on that being, it will be compelled to do.
Its aim and historical action is irrevocably and obviously
demonstrated in its own life situation as well as in the whole
organisation of burgeons society today. There is no need to
dwell here upon the fact that a large part of the English and
French proletariat is already conscious of its historic
task and is constantly working to develop that consciousness
into complete clarity.” Karl Marx and Frederick Engels: The
Holy Family (Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing
House, 1956). pp.52-53.
Aside from the fact that Marx
and Engels were hardly in a position in 1844-1845 to produce a
mature theory of proletarian class consciousness and proletarian
organisation (to become aware of this, one need only compare the
last sentence of the above quotation with what Engels wrote
forty years later about the English working class), these lines
say the very opposite of what Plekhanov reads into them. They
say only that the social situation of the proletariat
prepares it for radical, revolutionary action, and that the
determination of the general socialist objective (the abolition
of private property) is “pre scribed” by its conditions of
life. In no way do they indicate, however, that the
proletariat’s “inhuman conditions of life” will somehow
mysteriously enable it to “spontaneously” assimilate all the
social sciences. Quite the opposite! (Concerning Plekhanov’s
article, see Samuel H. Baron’s Plekhanov
[Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1963], pp.248-253.)
16.
Today it is almost forgotten that the Russian socialist movement
too was founded largely by students and intellectuals, and that
around three-fourths of a century ago they were faced with a
problem similar to that of the revolutionary intelligentsia
today. Similar, but of course not identical: Today there is an
additional obstacle (the reformist, revisionist mass
organisations of the working class), as well as an additional
strength (historical experience, including the experience of
great victory which the revolutionary movement has accumulated
since then).
In What is to Be Done?
Lenin speaks explicitly of the capacity of intellectuals to
assimilate “political knowledge,” i.e., scientific Marxism.
17.
Cf. Karl Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy. An
absorbing descriptions of the various early forms of trade
unions and of workers resistance funds can be found in E.P.
Thompson’s The Making of the English Working Class
(Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1968).
18.
The necessarily discontinuous nature of mass action is explained
by the class condition of the proletariat itself. As long as a
mass action does not succeed in toppling the capitalist mode of
production, its duration will be limited by the financial,
physical and mental ability of the workers to withstand the loss
of wages. It is obvious that this ability is not unlimited. To
deny this would be to deny the material conditions of the
proletariat’s existence, which compel it, as a class, to sell
its labour power.
19.
See a few examples from the first years of the metal workers
union of Germany: Fünfundsiebzig Jahre
Industriegewerkschaft Metall (Frankfurt: Europaische
Verlaganstalt, 1966), pp.72-78.
20.
We cannot describe in detail here the differences between a
prerevolutionary and a revolutionary situation. Simplifying the
matter, we would differentiate a revolutionary from a
prerevolutionary situation in this way: While a prerevolutionary
situation is characterised by such extensive mass struggles that
the continued existence of the social order is objectively
threatened, in a revolutionary situation this threat takes the
form, organisationally, of the proletariat establishing organs
of dual power (i.e., potential organs for the exercising of
power by the working class), and subjectively of the
masses raising directly revolutionary demands that the
ruling class is unable to either repulse or co-opt.
21.
See below the Leninist origins of this strategy.
22.
Rosa Luxemburg, Organisational Question of Social
Democracy, in Mary-Alice Waters, ed., Rosa
Luxemburg Speaks (New York: Pathfinder Press, 1970),
pp.112-130.
23.
Lenin, What is to Be Done?, op. cit.,
p.66.
24.
For a relating of this plan directly to revolution, see What
is to Be Done?, op. cit., pp.165-166.
It is true that there are also organisational rules for
centralisation in What is to Be Done?, but they
are determined exclusively by the conditions imposed by
illegality. Lenin recommends the broadest “democratism” for
“legal” revolutionary parties: “The general control (in
the literal sense of the term) exercised over every act of a
party man in the political field brings into existence an
automatically operating mechanism which produces what in biology
is called the ‘survival of the fittest.’ ‘Natural
selection’ by full publicity, election and general control
provides the assurance that, in the last analysis, every
political figure will be ‘in his proper place,’ do the work
for which he is best fitted by his powers and abilities, feel
the effects of his mistakes on himself, and prove before all the
world his ability to recognise mistakes and to avoid them.” Ibid.,
p.130.
Within her Polish party, which
was also defined by highly conspiratorial restrictions,
Luxemburg, for her part, practised (or accepted) a centralism
that was no less stringent than that of the Bolsheviks (cf. the
conflict with the Radek faction in Warsaw and the serious
charges made against it).
25.
Rosa Luxemburg Speaks, op. cit.,
p.118.
26.
For this see David Lane, The Roots of Russian Communism
(Assen: Van Gorcum and Co., 1969). Lane has attempted to analyse
the social composition of the membership of the Russian Social
Democracy and of the Bolshevik and Menshevik factions between
1897 and 1907 on the basis of empirical data. He comes to the
conclusion that the Bolsheviks had more worker members and
activists than the Mensheviks (pp.50-51).
27.
“Generally speaking it is undeniable that a strong tendency
toward centralisation is inherent in the social-democratic
movement. This tendency springs from the economic makeup of
capitalism which is essentially a centralising factor. The
social-democratic movement carries on its activity inside the
large bourgeois city. Its mission is to represent, within the
boundaries of the national state, the class interests of the
proletariat, and to oppose those common interests to all local
and group interests.
“Therefore, the social
democracy is, as a rule, hostile to any manifestations of
localism or federalism. It strives to unite all workers and all
worker organisations in a single party, no matter what national,
religious, or occupational differences may exist among them.” Rosa
Luxemburg Speaks, op. cit., p.116.
28.
Cf. the thesis put forward by Andre Gorz, according to which a
new party can be created only “from the bottom up” once the
network of factory and rank-and-file groups “stretches out
over the entire national territory.” (Ni Trade-Unionists,
ni Bolcheviks, Les Temps Moderne,
[October, 1969]). Gorz has not understood that the crisis of the
bourgeois state and the capitalist mode of production does not
develop gradually “from the periphery toward the centre,”
but that it is a discontinuous process which tends toward a
decisive test of strength once it reaches a definite turning
point. If the centralisation of revolutionary groups and
combatants does not take place in time, attempts by the
reformist bureaucracy to steer the movement back into acceptable
channels will only be facilitated – as quickly happened in
Italy, in fact while Gorz was writing his article. This in turn
quickly led to a setback for the “rank-and-file” groups. It
did not at all lead to their spread throughout the whole
country.
29.
Cf. Rosa Luxemburg’s article on the founding of the Communist
Party of Germany entitled The First Convention: “The
revolutionary shock troops of the German proletariat have joined
together into an independent political party.” (The
Founding Convention of the Communist Party of Germany
[Frankfort: Europaische Verlangastalt, 1969], p.301.) “From
now on it is a question of everywhere replacing revolutionary
moods with unflinching revolutionary convictions, the
spontaneous with the systematic.” (p.303.) See also (on p.301)
the passage from the pamphlet written by Luxemburg, What
Does the Spartacus League Want?: “The Spartacus
League is not a party that seeks to come to power over or with
the help of the working masses. The Spartacus League is only
that part of the proletariat that is conscious of its goal.
It is that part which, at each step, points the working-class
masses as a whole toward their historic task, which, at each
separate stage of the revolution, represents the ultimate
socialist objective and, in all national questions, the
interests of the proletarian world revolution.” (Emphasis
added.) In 1904 Luxemburg had not yet understood the essence of
Bolshevism – that “that part of the proletariat that is
conscious of its goal” must be organised separately
from the “broad mass.” It is a complete confirmation of our
thesis that as soon as Luxemburg adopted the concept of the
vanguard party, she too was then accused by Social Democrats
(“left” Social Democrats at that) of wanting “the
dictatorship over the proletariat.” (Max Adler, Karl
Liebknicht und Rosa Luxemburg, Der Kampf,
Vol.XII. No.2 [February, 1919], p.75.)
30.
Leon Trotsky, Nos taches politiques (Paris:
Editions Pierre Belfond, 1970), pp.123-129.
31.
Ibid., p.125.
32.
Ibid., p.186.
33.
Leon Trotsky, The Class, the Party and the Leadership, Fourth
International [predecessor of the International
Socialist Review] Vol.1, No.7 (December, 1940), p.193.
34.
Numerous examples of this could be mentioned, See, among others,
Lenin, Collected Works, Vol.18 (Moscow: Foreign
Languages Publishing House, 1963), pp.471-477; Vol.23,
pp.236-253; Vol.10, pp.277-278.
35.
The impossibility of “spontaneous” concentration of the
revolutionary vanguard elements on a national scale was
demonstrated with particular clarity in the French general
strike of May 1968.
36.
Yet here too these initial forms of independent organisation
were unable, in the absence of an organised revolutionary
vanguard, which would have carried out the necessary preparatory
work, to neutralise for long, let alone to smash, the
conservative centralisation of the trade-union and state
apparatuses, and of the entrepreneurs.
37.
Leon Trotsky, The History of the Russian Revolution
(Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1957), p.xix.
38.
See among others Georg Lukacs, Geschichte und
Klassenbewusstsein (Berlin: Malik-Verlag, 1923),
pp.180-189 ff.
39.
The defence of the political and material special interests of
these bureaucracies is nevertheless the social substructure upon
which the superstructure of this autonomy and its ideological
sediment are able to arise.
40.
Rosa Luxemburg Speaks, op. cit.,
p.12l.
41.
Leon Trotsky, Results and Prospects in The
Permanent Revolution, op. cit., p.114.
42.
Cf. for instance, Klara Zetkin’s biting scorn for the SPD
executive committee (as well as Kautsky’s lack of character),
which she expressed in her correspondence concerning the party
leadership’s censorship in 1909 of the publication of
Kautsky’s The Road to Power: K. Kautsky Le
Chemin de Pouvoir (Paris: Editions Anthropos, 1969),
pp.177-212. Contrast this with the respect shown by Lenin for
Kautsky in the same year.
43.
Lenin, Der Zusammenbruch der II. Internationale in
Lenin and Zinoviev, Gegen den Strom (published
by the Communist International, 1921), p.164.
44.
Ibid., p.165.
45.
Lenin, Left Wing Communism, an Infantile Disorder
in Collected Works, Vol.31 (Moscow: Foreign
Languages Publishing House, 1966). Pp.17-118.
See also the above-mentioned
passage from the pamphlet What Does the Spartacus League
Want?, written by Rosa Luxemburg.
This conclusion was, superior
to that of Trotsky in 1906 or Luxemburg in 1904. In the face of
a growing conservatism on the part of the social-democratic
apparatus, they had illusions about the ability of the masses to
solve the problem of the seizure of power with the aid of their
revolutionary ardour alone. In The Mass Strike, the
Political Party and the Trade Unions, (in Rosa
Luxemburg Speaks, op. cit.,
pp.153-219) Luxemburg even shifts the problem temporarily onto
the “unorganised,” i.e., the poorest, section of the
proletariat that for the first time attains consciousness during
a mass strike. In his writings after 1914 Lenin too explicitly
contrasts these masses to the “labour aristocracy,” in a
somewhat oversimplified manner, in my opinion. At that time the
workers in the large steel and metal processing plants, among
others, belonged to the unorganised sectors of the German
proletariat, and while they turned to the left en masse
after 1918, they did not at all belong to the “poorest”
layers.
46.
This so-called general crisis of capitalism, i.e., the onset of
the historical epoch of the decline of capitalism, should not be
confused with conjunctural crises, i.e., periodic economic
crises. These have occurred during the period of rising, as well
as declining, capitalism, For Lenin, the epoch beginning with
the first world war is the “era of beginning social
revolution.” See, among others, Gegen den Strom,
op. cit., p.393.
47.
Herein undoubtedly lies the greatest weakness of this fatalistic
theory. Out of the tendency toward growing autonomy, it
automatically deduces a social danger, without
including in its analysis the transmission of potential social
power and specific social interests. The tendency for doormen
and cashiers to develop their own interests does not give them
power over banks and large firms – except for the “power”
of robbery, which is effective only under very specific
conditions. If the analysis of this tendency toward autonomy is
to have any social content, therefore, it must be accompanied by
a definition of these conditions.
48.
The formal rules of democratic centralism are, of course, part
of these prerequisites. These rules include the right of all
members to be completely informed about differences of opinion
in the leadership; the right to form tendencies and to present
contradictory points of view to the membership before leadership
elections and conventions; the regular convening of conventions;
the right to periodically revise majority decisions in the light
of subsequent experiences, i.e., the right of minorities to
periodically attempt to reverse decisions made by the majority;
the right of political initiative by minorities and members at
conventions; etc.
These Leninist norms of
democratic centralism were rather strikingly formulated in the
new party statutes drawn up before August 1968 in preparation
for the fourteenth convention of the Czechoslovakian CP. The
Moscow defenders of bureaucratic centralism reacted with the
invasion. In fact, this proposed return to Leninist norms of
democratic centralism was one of the most important “thorns”
in the side of the Soviet bureaucracy as far as the developments
in Czechoslovakia were concerned.
49.
Leon Trotsky, The History of the Russian Revolution,
op. cit.
50.
Between 1905 and 1917 the Bolshevik Party was educated in the
spirit of achieving the “democratic dictatorship of the
workers and peasants,” i.e., in the spirit of a formula with
its eye on the possibility of a coalition between a workers
party and a peasant party within the framework of capitalism –
foreseeing, in other words, a capitalist development of
Russian agriculture and industry. Lenin clung to this
possibility until late 1916. Only in 1917 did he realise that
Trotsky had been correct back in 1905 when he predicted that the
agrarian question could only be solved by the dictatorship of
the proletariat and the socialisation of the Russian economy.
Hartmut Mehringer (Introduction
historique in Trotsky, Nos taches politiques,
op. cit., pp.17-18, 34ff.) is completely wrong
to link Lenin’s theory of organisation with his specific
strategy in the Russian revolution, to explain it in terms of
the “subordinate” role (?) of the working class in this
struggle, and to trace Trotsky’s theory of the gradual
extension of class consciousness to the entire working class to
the theory of the permanent revolution. Aside from the fact that
Mehringer gives an inadequate and inaccurate outline of
Lenin’s revolutionary strategy (Lenin was for the absolute
independence of the Russian working class in opposing the
Russian bourgeoisie, and was completely in favour of this class
playing a leading role in the revolution); and aside from the
fact that, like Lenin, Luxemburg rejected as premature any
attempt to establish the proletarian dictatorship in Russia and
assigned the revolutionary struggle of the Russian proletariat
the mere goal of carrying out the historical tasks of the
bourgeois revolution (while at the same time she fought against
Lenin’s theory of organisation). It appears obvious to us that
the very theory of permanent revolution (i.e., the task of
establishing the proletarian dictatorship in an underdeveloped
country) can be grasped with a minimum of realism only through
the utmost concentration on the revolutionary tasks in general.
Thus it leads not away from Lenin’s theory of organisation but
straight to it. See in this regard also the excellent pamphlet
by Demise Avenas, Economie et politique dans la pensee
de Trotsky (Paris: Maspero, “Cahiers Rouges,”
1970).
51.
Lenine, Oeuvres Completes, Tome 12 (Paris:
Editions Sociales, 1969), p.74.
“The pamphlet What is
to Be Done repeatedly emphasises that the organisation
of professional revolutionaries which it proposes makes sense
only insofar as it is connected to the ‘truly revolutionary
class irresistibly rising up in struggle.’” Lenin underlines
the fact that the sickness of small group existents can only be
overcome through “the ability of the party, through its own
mass work, to reach out to proletarian elements.” (Ibid.,
p.75.)
52.
Maspero in Paris will soon publish a: anthology by us entitled Workers
Control, Workers Councils and Workers Self-Management
which attempts to prove this thesis. Europäischer Verlaganstalt
has announced plans to publish a German edition in 1971.
53.
For Lenin the “leading role of the party” in the soviet
system is a political one, not one of substitution. It is a
question not of substituting itself for the majority in the
soviet, but of convincing them of the correctness of the
communist policy. The “leading role of the party” is not
even mentioned in his basic work on soviets, State and
Revolution. And if, in times of the greatest confusion
and civil war, he sometimes made sharp sallies on tactical
questions, arguments can be found in his writings against
“soviets without communists,” but no arguments in favour of
“communists without soviets.”
54.
Georg Lukacs (Geschichte und Klassenbewusstsein,
op. cit., p.306ff.) is wrong to think that he
discovers one of the roots of Luxemburg’s “theory of
spontaneity” in “the illusion of a purely proletarian
revolution.” Even in countries where the numerical and social
importance of the proletariat is so overwhelming that the
question of “allies” becomes insignificant, the separate
organisation of the vanguard remains absolutely necessary in a
“purely proletarian revolution” because of the internal
stratification of the proletariat.
55.
A striking example of this are the Chinese Maoists, for whom one
wing of their own party (including the majority of the central
committee that led the Chinese revolution to victory) is said to
be made up of “defenders of the capitalist line” – and
even “capitalists” pure and simple.
For the Italian Bordigists, the
general strike of July 14, 1948, had nothing to do with
proletarian class struggle because the workers were striking in
defence of the “revisionist” leader of the CP, Togliatti.
Cf. also the lovely formulation
of the French spontaneist Denis Anthier: “When the proletariat
is not revolutionary, it does not exist, and revolutionaries
cannot do anything with it. It is not they who, by assuming the
role of educators of the people, will be able to create the
historical situation in which the proletariat will become what
it is; this can only be done by the development of modern
society itself.” (Preface to Leon Trotsky, Rapport
de la delegation siberienne [Paris: Spartacus
1970], p.12.) This quote also shows how clearly extreme
subjectivity and extreme objectivism are related. And how is it
explained that despite huge struggles the proletariat does not
achieve victory? “Circumstances are to blame, the objective
conditions were not ripe.” Behind the ultraleft mask one can
see those well-known “spontaneists” Karl Kautsky and Otto
Bauer eagerly nodding their wise heads. The ridiculous
conclusions to which this extreme fatalism and mechanical
determinism lead become clear as soon as the “development of
modern society itself” is expected to explain to us in
concrete terms just why at a given moment the majority of
factory A and city B (but not of factory C or city D) come out
in favour of the dictatorship of the proletariat and against
reformism. Yet for better or for worse, the outcome of the
revolution depends upon the answer to this question. As long as
the “development of modern society itself” does not drop all
factories and all cities like ripe fruit into the lap
of the revolution, the “educators of the people,” according
to Anthier, should presumably refrain from doing violence to
“objective conditions,” by seeking to win over the workers
of C and D.
56.
This reproach against Lenin and the Leninists was made by the
Russian “Economists,” and now today’s spontaneists have
rediscovered it.
57.
Cf. on this subject Nicos Poulantzas, Pouvoir politique,
et classes sociales, op. cit.
58.
It is interesting to confirm that after the split in the Russian
Social Democracy there were many more intellectuals, including
professional revolutionary intellectuals, with the Mensheviks
than with the Bolsheviks. See in this connection David Lane, The
Roots of Russian Communism, op. cit.,
pp.47-50.
59.
David Lane too emphasises the preponderance of the Bolsheviks in
the cities with large factories and an old, stabilised working
class, Ibid., pp.212-213.)
60.
In his last work (Zum allgemeinen Verhaltnis von
wissenschaftlicher Intelligenz und proletarischen
Klassenbewusstsein, SDS-Info, No.2127
[Dec. 22, 1969]), Hans-Jurgen Krahl brought out “the Marx
quotation on this question which we are reprinting here. (It
comes from the unincorporated section Sechstes Kapitel,
Resultate des unmittelbaren Produktionsprozesses in the
draft of Chapter Six of Book One of the first volume of Capital,
which was published for the first time, in the Marx-Engels
Archives in 1933.) We should like to dedicate this
article, which was intended to promote discussion and
understanding with him, to this young friend who so tragically
passed away.
“With the development of a
real subsuming of labour under capital (or in the specifically
capitalist mode of production) the real functionary in the
overall labour process is not the individual worker, but
increasingly a combined social capacity for work, and the
various capacities for work, which are in competition with one
another and constitute the entire productive machine,
participate in very different ways in the direct process of
creating commodities – or, more accurately in this sense,
products – (one works more with his hands, another more with
his head, one as a manager, an engineer, a technician, etc.,
another as a supervisor, and a third as a simple manual
labourer, or even a helper). As a result of this, the functions
of labour capacity will increasingly tend to be classified by
the direct concept of productive labour, while those who possess
that capacity will be classified under the concept of productive
workers, directly exploited by capital and subordinated to its
process of consumption and production.” ( Karl Marx, Resultate
[Frankfurt: Neue Kritik, 1969], p.66.)
61.
Leon Trotsky, The Intelligentsia and Socialism
( London: New Park Publishers, 1966).
62.
Leon Trotsky, Die Entwicklungstendenzen der russischen
Sozioldemkratie, in Die Neue Zeit
Vol.XXVIII, No.2 (1910), p.862.
63.
Already in his first polemical book against Lenin ( Nos
taches politiques, op. cit., pp.68-71,
for example), Trotsky had undertaken an effort to represent the
entire Leninist polemic against “economism” and the
“handicraftsman’s approach to organisation” in What
is to Be Done? as a pure discussion between
intellectuals, or at best an attempt to win over the best forces
of the petty-bourgeois intelligentsia to the revolutionary
Social Democracy. He did not understand that it was a question
of repelling the petty-bourgeois, revisionist influence upon
the working class. His polemic against Lenin from 1903 to
1914 was characterised by an underappreciation of the
catastrophic consequences of opportunism for the working class
and the labour movement. Only in 1917 did he overcome this
underappreciation once and for all.
64.
August Bebel, Briefwechsel mit Friedrich Engels
(The Hague: Mouton and Co., 1965), p.465.
65.
The sole difficulty for the revolution seemed to them to lie in
a necessary reaction to any possible repeal of universal
suffrage, as might happen in case of war. In contrast, Luxemburg
had, in dealing with the question of the mass strike, undertaken
a conscious attempt to develop the proletariat’s forms of
struggle by going beyond electoral and wage struggles and
closely following the example of the Russian revolution of 1905.
Even today, Lelio Basso, in an
interesting analysis of Rosa Luxemburgs Dialektik der
Revolution (Frankfurt: Europaische Verlagsanstalt,
1969), pp.82-83, attempts to present as the quintessence of
Luxemburg’s strategy a centrist reconciliation between
day-to-day struggles and ultimate objectives which is limited to
“sharpening the contradictions” of objective development.
The fact that the deeper meaning of the mass strike strategy
escapes him as a result of this error does not need to be dwelt
on here in detail.
66.
See the discussion of program at the fourth congress of the
Communist International (Protokoll des Vierten
Kongresses der Kommunistischen Internationale
[published by the Communist International, 1923], pp.404-448).
It provisionally concluded with the following declaration of the
Russian delegation, signed by Lenin, Trotsky, Zinoviev, Radek
and Bukharin: “The dispute over how the transitional demands
should be formulated and in which section of the program they
should be included has awakened a completely erroneous
impression that there exists a principled difference. In light
of this, the Russian delegation unanimously confirms that the
drawing up of transitional slogans in the programs of the
national sections and their general formulation and theoretical
motivation in the general section of the program cannot be
interpreted as opportunism.” (Ibid., p.542.)
Trotsky seemed to foresee such a strategy already in 1904 when
he wrote: “The party stands on the proletariat’s given
lack of consciousness ... and attempts to implant itself in
the proletariat by raising this level ...” (Nos
taches politiques, op. cit., p.126.)
67.
Georg Lukacs (Lenine, [Paris: E.D.I., 1965],
p.57) is completely correct when he concludes from similar
considerations that the Leninist revolutionary party cannot
“make” a revolution, but can accelerate the tendencies that
will lead to one. Such a party is both producer and
product of the revolution – which amounts to a resolution of
the antithetical positions of Kautsky (“The new party must
prepare the way for the revolution”) and Luxemburg (“The new
party will be created by the revolutionary action of the
masses”).
68.
Hans-Jurgen Krahl (op. cit., p.13ff.) is quite
correct when he reproaches Lukacs for his “idealising”
concept of the totality of proletarian class consciousness, and
when he accuses him of an inability to combine empirical
knowledge and abstract theory – itself based on an inability
to transmit revolutionary theory to the working masses. He
should have been able to conclude from our essay, however, that
such a transmission can be completely achieved on the basis of
the Leninist concept of organisation – that it, in fact, lies
at the very heart of this concept. Since he makes a sharp
distinctions between “alienated lot in life” and alienated
process of production, however, he is predisposed by the
Marcusian tendency to see the “alienation of the consumer”
as the central problem, and as a result to regard the
“civilised satisfaction of needs,” which the neo-capitalist
system ostensibly makes possible for the working class, as an
obstacle on its way toward acquiring proletarian class
consciousness. Yet the Achilles heel of the capitalist mode of
production must more than ever be sought in the sphere of
alienation in the production process; there alone can a truly
revolutionary rebellion begin, as the events in France and Italy
have demonstrated. With that we are brought back to the process,
which we described, of formulating and conveying class
consciousness. In describing it we, like Krahl (and, we are
convinced, like Lenin and Trotsky), in no way substitute the
naive concept of the “omniscient party” for that of the
evolution of revolutionary theory as a specific and
permanent ongoing process of production.
69.
Karl Marx, Theses on Feuerbach, third thesis: “The
materialist doctrine concerning the changing of circumstances
and upbringing forgets that circumstances are changed by men and
that it is essential to educate the educators themselves.”
(Marx-Engels, The German Ideology, op.
cit., p.660.)
70.
Ibid., p.234.
|