The Cuban magazine Nueva Industria –
Revista Economica, organ of the Ministry of Industry,
published two polemical articles in issue No.? (October 1963) of
great interest, one written by Ernesto Che Guevara and the other
by Commandante Alberto Mora, Minister of Foreign Trade. This
polemic testifies to the vitality of the Cuban Revolution in the
field of Marxist theory, too. It deals with a number of
questions of the utmost importance in the construction of a
socialist economy: role of the law of value in the economy
during the epoch of transition; autonomy of enterprises and
self-management; investments through the budget or by means of
self-investment, etc. Involved in these issues is the problem of
the ideal model for the economy in the epoch of transition from
an underdeveloped country, a problem of absorbing interest to
the Bolsheviks during the 1923-1928 period and which arose again,
even if on a rather low theoretical level, in Yugoslavia, Poland
and even in the Soviet Union in recent years.
The Law of Value in the Economy During the
Epoch of Transition
The question of the “application” of the
theory of value in the planned and socialized economy of the
epoch of transition has been subjected to the worst confusion,
mainly because Stalin, in his last work, posed it in a both
gross and simplistic way: “Does the law of value exist (sic)
and does it apply in our country? … Yes, it exists there and it
applies there.” This is an evident truism. To the extent that
exchange occurs, commodity production survives, and exchange is
thereby objectively governed by the law of value. The latter
cannot disappear until commodity production withers away; that
is, with the production of an abundance of goods and services.
But this does not answer the concrete
question around which turns the fundamental discussion
begun in 1924-25 between Preobrazhensky and Bukharin which has
continued to develop, with ups and downs, among Marxist
economists and theoreticians up to now: to what exact degree
and in what sphere does the law of value apply in the
economy during the epoch of transition?
Stalin himself, while muddying the problem,
had to admit a fact which the Khrushchevist economists are
nevertheless beginning to draw into question; namely, that in
the “socialist” economy, the law of labour-value cannot be the
regulator of production, that is, cannot determine
investments.
In developed capitalist economy, the law of
value determines production through the play of the rate of
profit. Capital flows toward the sectors where the rate of
profit is above the average and production increases there.
Capital recedes from the sectors where the rate of profit is
below the average, and production decreases there (at least
relatively). When the means of production are nationalized, so
that there is neither a market for capital nor its free entry
and withdrawal, nor even the formation of an average rate of
profit with which the rate of each particular branch can be
compared, clearly there is no longer a possibility for the “law
of value” to be directly the “regulator of production.”
If, in an underdeveloped country which has
carried out its socialist revolution, the “law of value” were to
regulate investments, there would flow preferentially toward the
sectors where profitability is the highest in relation to
prices on the world market. But it is precisely because
these prices determine a concentration of investments in the
production of raw materials that these countries are
underdeveloped. To escape from underdevelopment, to
industrialize the country, means to deliberately orient
investments toward the sectors that are least “profitable” for
the time-being according to the criterion of the long-term
economic and social development of the country as a whole. When
it is said that the monopoly of foreign trade is indispensable
for industrializing the under-developed countries, this means
precisely that it cannot be accomplished until these countries
are able to “pull the teeth” of the law of value.
But perhaps this qualification applies only
to the “law of value on the world market”? Cannot the law of
value at least alter investments on the national scale, once
world prices are left aside? This is wrong again. The
industrialization of an underdeveloped country cannot be carried
out rapidly and harmoniously except by deliberately violating
the law of value. [1]
In an underdeveloped country, and precisely
because of its underdevelopment, agriculture tends from the
beginning to be more “profitable” than industry, handicrafts and
small industry more “profitable” than big industry, light
industry more “profitable” than heavy industry, the private
sector more “profitable” than the nationalized sector. To
channel investments according to the “law of value,” that is,
according to the law of supply and demand of commodities
produced by different branches of the economy, would imply
developing monoculture for the export trade by priority; it
would imply preferential construction of small shops for the
local market rather than steel plants for the national market.
The construction of comfortable lodgings for the petty-bourgeois
or bureaucratic layers (an investment corresponding to
“effective demand”) would have priority over the construction of
low-cost homes for the people which clearly must be subsidized.
In short, all the economic and social evils of underdevelopment
would be reproduced despite the victory of the revolution.
In reality, the decisive meaning of this
victory, of the nationalization of the means of industrial
production, of credit, of the transportation system and foreign
trade (together with the monopoly of the latter), is precisely
to create the conditions for a process of industrialization
that escapes from the logic of the law of value. Economic,
social and political priorities, consciously and
democratically chosen, take the lead over the law of value
in order to lay out the successive stages of industrialization.
Priority is placed not on immediate maximum returns, but on the
suppression of rural unemployment, the reduction of
technological backwardness, the suppression of the foreign grip
on the national economy, the guarantee of the rapid social and
cultural rise of the masses of workers and poor peasants, the
rapid suppression of epidemics and endemic diseases, etc., etc.
That is why the industrialization of the
workers states follows a different road from that of the
capitalist countries where industries are built beginning with
the sectors that will most easily satisfy “effective demand.”
To violate the law of value is one thing; to
disregard it is something else again. The economy of a
workers state can disregard the law of value only at the price
of losses to the economy which could be avoided, of
useless sacrifices imposed on the masses, as we shall later
demonstrate.
What does this mean? In the first place, that
the whole economy must be carried on within the framework of a
strict calculation of the real costs of production. These costs
will not determine investments; these will not automatically go
toward “the least costly” projects. But to know the costs means
to know the exact amount of subsidies which the collectivity
grants the sectors which it has decided to develop by priority.
In the second place, that it is necessary to have a stable
yardstick for these calculations; without stable money, no
rigorous planning. In the third place, that all sectors where
economic or social priorities do not dictate any preference are
to be actually guided by the “law of value,” (for example,
different crops aiming at the domestic market). In the fourth
place, so longs as the means of consumption remain commodities,
and aside from the commodities and services deliberately
subsidized or distributed free by the state (pharmaceutical
products, school and training materials, books, etc.), the
preferences of the consumers will freely operate on the market
the law of supply and demand will affect prices, and the plan
will adapt its projected investments to these oscillations (within
the limits of what is available in finances, equipment, raw
materials, etc.).
In the light of these initial remarks, we can
consider the importance of the two problems raised in the
Guevara-Mora polemic: What is value? Are means of production
commodities in the transitional epoch? Mora affirms that value
is not essentially abstract human labour; that it is “a relation
existing between the limited disposable resources and the
growing needs of man” (p.15). Still better: he holds that value
is a “category created by man under certain conditions and for
certain (!) ends” (p.15).
It is clear that we are faced here with a
subjective deformation of the Marxist concept of
labour-value, of which Marx specified the essence to be
abstract human labour. It is not by chance that Mora refers
to the “neo-Marxist” Soviet economists
[2], who have been attacked,
in the USSR itself, and rightly so, as wanting to introduce
surreptitiously the marginal theory of value. His conception,
according to which the “law of value is the economic criterion
for regulating production” in the epoch of transition (p.17) –
while he affirms that it is not the only regulator –
necessarily involves the notion according to which “exchange of
the means of production” occurs even when these are completely
nationalized, that “sale of commodities” occurs even when these
means of production pass from one nationalized enterprise to
another, and that the “contradictions” between the state
enterprises justify the assertion that a “change in ownership”
occurs at the time of these exchanges (p.19). All these
affirmations are contrary to the reality and to Marxist theory.
On all these questions, Che Guevara is entirely right against
Mora.
Mora states that if in investments, one
leaves aside the law of value, one must “pay the price”; in
doing this, you automatically limit the social resources
available to satisfy other needs. This is true, and we, likewise,
underline the necessity for strict calculation of production
costs in all fields. But in limiting oneself to this economic
truth, the social content of the epoch of transition is done
away with; that is, in abstracting from the class struggle,
Mora leaves out a whole important side of the problem.
In fact, it is impossible to operate in the
economy of the epoch of transition – any more than in any other
economy containing different social classes – with aggregates
like “social revenue,” “social costs,” “social price of
investments,” without at the same time posing the question: “Who
is to pay this price to whom?
The society of the epoch of the transition to
capitalism to socialism is not homogeneous. In conducting an
appropriate policy of investments, of prices, wages, foreign
trade, etc., the workers state can act in such a way that the
social benefits of priority investments (numerical
reinforcement of the working class; elevation of its standard of
living, skill, culture and consciousness; reinforcement of its
leading role in the state and economy; accentuation of its
participation in political life, etc., etc.) are paid
economically by other social classes; the residue of the
former owning classes; imperialism; the small commercial
entrepreneurs and independent peasants. In an expanding economy,
this economic price, paid particularly by the merchants,
artisans and independent peasants can moreover be accompanied by
a rise in their standard of living, on condition that this rise
is less than it would have been in the framework of the “free
play of the law of value” (thanks, for example, to a progressive
income tax). [3]
The Law of Value and Foreign Trade
All the preceding evidently constitutes only
a general framework for replying to the specific problems which
the question of economic calculation and the orientation of
investments raises in each particular workers state. Here, Mora
is right when he stresses (p.18) that in a small country like
Cuba, which depends strictly on foreign trade for the current
functioning of its industry (spare parts and raw materials) and
for the equipment of its new enterprises, the necessity for
rigorous economic calculation is imposed with all the more
reason than in a big, largely autarchic country like the Soviet
Union.
Exports are made according to prices on the
world market. So that these exports will not constitute a
constant drain on the national economy (they must be met in any
case in order to keep industry and industrialization going
through imports), it is necessary that the production costs of
exported goods should as a whole be below the prices obtained on
the world market. It is necessary to fix the objective on
progressively suppressing all exports at a loss, so that exports
are not only a means supplying the national economy but, in
addition, an important source of accumulation, a means of
defraying part of the expense of industrialization – a part of
the costs of not observing the law of value on the national
market! – from abroad. The tendency for current prices of sugar
to rise on the world market creates, moreover, a favorable
framework for the success of such a policy. The progressive
diversification of exports, to render the Cuban economy
independent of future fluctuations of current sugar prices on
the world market, must point to the selection of other export,
products where production costs remain below the prices obtained
abroad (that is, average prices on the world market).
But Mora mixes up the need to carry out all
these calculations in the most strict way with the extension of
the field of application of the law of value in the Cuban
economy. The two phenomena are not identical; they can even be
directly contradictory.
The law of value determines the exchange
value of commodities according to the quantity of labour
socially necessary to produce them. The concept of “socially
necessary” labour is determined in turn by the average level of
the productivity of labour in a country, and by the concept of
the effective demand of society – which must never be confounded
with human needs or social needs from an objective point of
view. In an underdeveloped country like Cuba, all
production of many industrial branches can correspond to an
“effective demand,” that is, all labour in these branches can
appear as “socially necessary,” despite a very low level of
productivity. The reference to the law of value, far from
thereby resolving the problem of rapid improvement in the
productivity of labour, of the technological transformations
which these industries must undergo, can only obscure it.
Because the law of value will have a tendency to keep alive
archaic enterprises, as long as the state of scarcity exists,
from the moment there ceases to be free movement of capital and
free imports of commodities which could stimulate competition
with these enterprises.
Far from being a field of application of the
law of value, the dependence of Cuba on foreign trade thus
implies the necessity of economic calculation of comparative
international costs, which could provide a choice of
economic criteria, independently of any rigid “law.” The
necessity to assure the country’s supply of spare parts and raw
materials imposes a certain volume of exports, even if
these are carried out at a loss. The necessity to maintain and
develop the existing level of industries dependent on foreign
supplies imposes searching, as quickly as possible, for
profitable exports in relation to prices on the world market
– even if this means switching investments toward branches that
are already profitable in relation to the national market
(branches that already sell their commodities at their exchange
value). The possibility of exporting at a profit, of gaining
supplementary resources from exports, of transforming trade into
a constant source of socialist accumulation, will moreover
permit just the liberation of the economy from the
tyranny of the “law of value,” that is, will permit the
development of new industries despite the fact that their
production costs at the beginning will be higher than the prices
of imported products, without lowering the standard of living or
the rate of accumulation in the country. This is an aspect of
the real dialectics of the dependence on foreign trade and the
play of the law of value that is decidedly more complex than
Comrade Mora thought!
The Law of Value and Autonomy of Decision
at the Enterprise Level
In the debate which has raged in some of the
workers states, the problem of the area of application of the
law of value is intimately linked with the problem of autonomy
of decision at the enterprise level in the field of investment.
The Yugoslav authors have even formulated with regard to this a
veritable new dogma which requires critical analysis: “Without
the right of the self-management collectives to dispose of a
considerable part of the social surplus product, no genuine
self-management.” [4] This
analysis must examine the problem from two aspects: economic
efficiency (criteria for choosing one investment project rather
than another), social and political efficiency (success in the
struggle against the bureaucracy and bureaucratization).
The more backward a country is, the more
conditions of almost universal scarcity rule not only in the
means of production sector but also for much of the industrial
means of consumption (at least for the great majority of the
population), and the more detrimental the practice of
self-investment is, the more detrimental is it to permit
the self-management collectives to determine for themselves the
projects for priority of productive investments.
It is evident in fact that under conditions
of almost general scarcity of industrial commodities, almost
all the investment projects can be economically profitable,
no matter how gross the economic errors that are committed.
Almost every profitable industrial or agricultural enterprise (providing
funds for investment) is like an island in a sea of unsatisfied
needs. The natural tendency of self-investment is therefore to
attend to what is most pressing, both locally and in each
sector.
In other words: if the self-management
enterprises hold large funds for self-investment, they will have
a tendency to orient their investments either toward the
commodities which they lack the most (certain equipment goods;
raw materials; auxiliary products; emergency sources of energy),
or toward the commodities which their workers or the inhabitants
of the area lack the most. Thus, criteria of local or sector
interest are placed above national interests, not because the
law of value is “denied,” but precisely because it is
applied! This means, once more, to orient industrialization
toward the “traditional road” which it followed in the historic
framework of capitalism, in place of reorienting it according to
the requirements of a nationally planned economy.
An attempt can be made to reconcile national
planning requirements and allocating self-managed enterprises
considerable funds for self-investment. The means chosen for
this aim can be a levy-tax in behalf of national development
funds and equalization funds for regional development. This is
evidently a step in the right direction, but it does not at all
resolve the problem.
Since an underdeveloped economy is
characterized precisely by the fact that the enterprises of high
productivity are still the exception and not the rule, it is
sufficient to leave them a part of their net surplus product and
the inequality of development between the industrialized
localities and the non-industrialized localities, the inequality
of development and of revenue between the archaic enterprises
which enjoy only an average level of productivity and the
enterprises technologically “up to date” will increase instead
of diminishing. It is necessary, moreover, to insist on
this fundamental idea of Marxism: any economic freedom, any
“autonomy of decision” and any “spontaneity” increases the
inequality so long as there exist side by side strong and
feeble enterprises or individuals, rich and poor, favored and
unfavored from the point of view of location, etc. This is the
reason why, it should be noted in passing, that according to
Marx the mechanism of the law of value leads to its own
negation; competition inevitably ends in monopoly.
The economic logic of a planned economy
therefore speaks completely in favor of productive
investment by budgetary means at least for all the big
enterprises. What must be left to the enterprises is an
amortization fund sufficiently large to permit modernization
of equipment with each renewal of fixed equipment (gross
investment). But all net investments should be made in
accordance with the plan, in the branches and places chosen
according to preferential criteria selected for the society and
its economy as a whole. In this respect, too, the thesis of
Comrade Guevara is correct.
The problem has been obscured, above all in
the USSR, through associating it with the problem of
heightening the material incentives in enterprises.
Numerous Soviet economists have criticized the stimulants still
employed today in the economy of the USSR to incite the
enterprises (?) to carry out the plans. This criticism is in
general pertinent. It has but to repeat what anti-Stalinist
Marxists have said critically for many years. Yet, it is only
necessary to examine closely the arguments of these economists
to see that what is involved in reality is heightening of
material incentives for the bureaucracy for whom the growth
of revenues must in some way be the essential stimulus for the
expansion of production in the enterprises.
This is where certain partisans of
self-management, particularly in Yugoslavia, maintain that
decentralization of the decisions on investment would be a
powerful guarantee against bureaucratization. This thesis
is based on a fallacy. The Yugoslavs are right in stressing that
the power of the bureaucracy grows in relation to its freedom in
disposing of the social surplus product. But the technicians and
economists of the planning commission “dispose” of the surplus
product only in the form of figures on paper; the real power of
disposal is situated at the level of the enterprise.
[5] The more that means
other than consumption funds (distributed revenues and social
investments) are left at the free disposal of the enterprises,
the more is precisely bureaucratization stimulated, at
least in a climate of generalized scarcity and poverty; also the
greater the temptation becomes for corruption, theft, abuse of
confidence, false entries – temptations that do not exist at the
level of the planning commission, if only because of multiple
checks. The concrete experience of Yugoslav “decentralization”
has shown, moreover, that it is an enormous source of inequality
and bureaucratization at the level of the enterprises.
But doesn’t the possibility of complete
centralization of the means of investment at the state level
create the danger of the economic policy as a whole
favoring the bureaucracy, as was the case in Stalinist Russia?
Obviously. But then the cause does not reside in the
centralization itself; it lies in the absence of workers
democracy on the national political level.
[6] This means that a
genuine guarantee against bureaucratization depends on workers
management at the enterprise level and workers democracy at the
state level. Without this combination, even the autonomy of the
enterprises will eliminate none of the authoritarian,
bureaucratic and (often) erroneous character of economic
decisions made at the government level of the plan. With this
combination, the centralization of investments – priorities
being democratically established, for example through a national
congress of workers councils – would not encourage
bureaucratization, but, on the contrary, suppress one of its
principle sources.
The Law of Value and Self-Management
“Heightening material incentives” in the
enterprises cannot be a “stimulant” in the question of
investments. But “heightening material incentives” in the
self-management collectives can actually stimulate continual
growth of production and productivity among the enterprises.
Certainly, under a regime of genuine
socialist democracy, creative enthusiasm, the free development
of all the capacities of invention and organization of the
proletariat, constitute a powerful motor for the growth of
production. But it would be a grave idealist and voluntarist
error to suppose that in a in a climate of poverty –
inevitable in an underdeveloped country immediately following
the victory of the socialist revolution – this enthusiasm could
last long without a sufficient material substructure.
The example of the Soviet Union, where the
proletariat gave proof of an enthusiasm and spirit of
self-sacrifice without parallel in the first years after the
October Revolution, is instructive in this respect: a long
period of deprivation ended inevitably in mounting passivity of
the workers, daily material concerns taking precedence over
attentiveness to meetings.
It is therefore imperative to link
self-management to the possibility for the workers to
immediately judge the success of each effort at increasing
production by the elevation of their standard of living.
The simplest and most transparent technique is that of
distributing a part of the net revenue of the enterprise among
the workers in the form of one or more months of bonus wages,
the amount increasing or diminishing automatically with the
level of revenue. The increasing collective material
interest of the workers in the management of the
enterprises moreover is superior to piece wages, inasmuch as it
does not introduce division and conflicts in the workers’
collectivity, inasmuch as it corresponds better to contemporary
technique, which place less and less importance on individual
output and more and more importance on the rational organization
of labour.
Self-management (and not mere workers control)
seems to be the ideal model for organizing socialist enterprises.
But it by no means hinders more or less unlimited competition
among the enterprises, which flows from their autonomy in the
domain of prices and investments. This autonomy cannot but
reproduce a series of evils inherent to the capitalist regime:
monopoly positions exploited in the formation of prices and
revenues; efforts to defend these monopolies by “hiding”
discoveries and technical improvements; waste and duplication in
the field of investments; high cost or errors in decision,
revealed a posteriori on the market (including the
shutting down of enterprises); reappearance of unemployment,
etc., etc. Useless and detrimental from the economic point of
view, it by no means constitutes a sufficient guarantee against
bureaucratization, as we have indicated above.
In this connection, the polemic of Lenin and
Trotsky against the theses of the “Workers Opposition” is still
completely valid. Marxism is not to be confused with the
doctrine of anarcho-syndicalism. The genuine guarantee of
workers power lies on the political level; it is on the state
level that it must be established; any other solution is
utopian; that is, unworkable in the long run and a source for
the reappearance of a powerful bureaucracy.
For all these reasons, self-management does
not at all imply wider recourse to the “law of value” in
relation to centralized planning.
[7] The fundamental data of
the problem remain the same. It is necessary to carry out strict
calculations of production costs to show in the case of each
commodity whether its production has been subsidized or not. But
nothing calls for the conclusion that prices must be “determined
by the law of value,” that is, by the law of supply and demand.
If such a conclusion still has some meaning with regard to the
means of consumption, it is senseless for the means of
production which, we repeat, are not commodities, at least in
the great majority of cases. And even means of production which
are still commodities – those produced by the private or
co-operative sector for the delivery to the state, and which the
state furnishes to private enterprises or co-operatives – cannot
be “sold at their value” without encouraging under certain
conditions private primitive accumulation at the expense of
socialist accumulation. But, if the means of production are not
sold “at their value,” the “value” of the means of consumption
is itself profoundly modified.
Prices are, then, instruments of socialist
planning and cannot be anything else in the epoch of transition
from capitalism to socialism. If you say instrument of planning
you likewise say instrument for determining the distribution
of the national revenue between consumption and investment, an
instrument for determining the distribution of revenues among
the different classes and layers of the nation. To leave
the determination of this distribution to the “law of value,” is
to leave it in the final analysis to the “laws of the market,”
to the “law of supply and demand,” that is, to economic
automatism. And economic automatism would rapidly take us back
to an economy of the semi-colonial type.
But to say that prices cannot be
determined by the law of value does not at all signify that
they can be independent of the latter. Society can
never distribute more values than it has created without
progressively destroying its accumulated wealth and
impoverishing itself increasingly in the absolute sense of the
term. The total sum of prices must therefore be equal to the
total sum of value of the commodities produced (granting that
there has been no monetary depreciation). The distribution of
certain products – in goods or vouchers – below their value
(subsidies!) automatically signifies a distribution of other
products above their value. Without strict calculation of
production costs; without book-keeping aided by an objective
criterion; without a kind of double entry system that faithfully
registers, for each product, alongside the price fixed by the
state, the real cost and the subsidy (or the tax) there is not
only no possibility for genuine scientific planning, there is
above all no stimulus for the fundamental economic dynamic of
the epoch of transition – the dynamic that progressively
elevates one new branch of industry after another to the point
of rendering it “competitive” in relation to prices on the world
market, up to the time socialism announces its next triumph when
socialist industry as a whole operates with a productivity
superior to that of the most advanced capitalist industry.
At the moment, the “law of value” could
theoretically govern the dynamic of the workers state (or more
exactly: the workers states as an international whole; because
it appears excluded that this situation could be first obtained
“in a single country”). But at the precise moment when it is on
the point of triumphing, its reason for being disappears. The
highest level of productivity attained under capitalism in all
its branches cannot be surpassed without approaching such a
level of abundance that commodity production withers away. In
the workers state “law of value” cannot channel investments
except to the precise degree that it withers away and to the
degree that along with it all the economic categories, products
of a relative scarcity of material resources, likewise wither
away.
Notes
1. “Planned economy in
the transitional period, while founded on the law of value,
violates it nevertheless at every step and establishes relations
among the different economic branches, and between industry and
agriculture in the first place, on the basis of equal exchange.
The state budget plays the role of a lever for forced
accumulation and planned distribution. This role must be
increased in accordance with the latest economic progress.
Credit financing dominates relations between the coercive
accumulation of the budget and the fluctuations of the market,
insofar as the latter enter in… If the domestic Soviet market is
‘freed’ and the monopoly of foreign trade suppressed – exchange
between the city and countryside will become much more equal,
the accumulation of the village (I refer to the capitalist
accumulation of the farmer, the ‘kulak’) will follow its course,
and it will soon be seen that Marx’s formulas likewise apply to
agriculture. Once on this road, Russia would rapidly become a
colony that would serve as the base for the industrial
development of other countries.” (Leon Trotsky: Stalin
Theoretician. Available in French in Ecrits 1928-40,
Tome I, p.106) [Available in English in different translations
as Stalin as a Theoretician in Militant,
15 September-11 December 1930 and Stalin as a Theoretician
in International Socialist Review, Fall 1956 &
Winter 1957.]
2. Among
others, Novochilov, Kantorovitch and Menchinov. This question
underlies the famous debate on the possible use of profit as the
sole criterion in carrying out the plan. In reality, these
economists are the spokesmen of the economic bureaucracy, who
demand increased rights for the directors of enterprises
– particularly the right to freely dispose of a part of the
“invisible funds” (fixed equipment).
3. From
1924 to 1927, the Stalinist faction violently accused the Left
Opposition – Preobrazhensky in particular – with wanting “to
increase the prices of industrial products.” Preobrazhensky had
simply proposed that industrial products could be sold “above
their value” to the village, which could have been tied in
perfectly with a progressive lowering of the sales price in view
of the rapid growth of the productivity of labour. But when the
Stalinist faction made the turn to accelerated
industrialization, it increased the prices of industrial
consumers goods through extremely high indirect taxes. While in
1928, the tax on turnover was not above 17.9% of the real
turnover of retail trade, it rose to 78.1% in 1932, and in 1936,
the nominal turnover of this trade was 107 billion rubles, of
which taxes accounted for 66 billion rubles and the real
turnover only 41 billion! (L.H. Hubbard: Trade and
Distribution in the Soviet Union)
4. Thus
Milentiji Popovic, in an article entitled Self-management
and Planning: “On the other hand, in the sector of expanded
social reproduction, in perfecting the system of investment on
the basis of the new relations, our results are less conclusive,
although the first steps have been taken in this direction. The
establishment of non-administrative relations, of economic
relations, in this sphere, reverts quite simply to the
establishment of credit-interest (!) relations, and to taking
them as the basis ...
“One must first of all counteract the
contradiction which arises from the fact that the resources
servicing social reproduction are deducted exclusively through
administrative measures (taxes, duties, contributions) thus
leaving free the organization of labour without the latter on
the other hand becoming the ‘proprietor;’ the organization of
labour evolves, in fact, into a unique system of credit in which
these resources are at one and the same time ‘theirs’ and
‘common’ (article 11) …
It is possible to avoid, on the other hand,
having subjective and political considerations as the only ones
to be taken into consideration at the time of the adoption of
the decisions concerning investments. It goes without saying
that this method cannot and must not ever be pushed to its final
conclusion. But a system can be constructed in which the
political decisions will bear on the general orientation of the
political economy while the distribution of the means destined
for investment is carried out in accordance with the credit
mechanism, according to financial and material (!) criteria
fixed with more or less precision. In operating in this way the
process of expanded reproduction is likewise ‘depoliticalised.’
This ‘depoliticalization’ is not absolute. It must be carried
out to the degree that bureaucratism must be deprived of its
base in this sphere as in the others.” (My emphasis – E.M.).
– Current Questions of Socialism, No.70,
July-Sept. 1963, pp.67-68.
5. This
obviously does not apply to cases where raw materials, equipment,
goods and sometimes even means of consumption are centrally
distributed, becoming veritable hotbeds for germinating
corrupted bureaucrats.
6. “Only
the co-ordination of three elements, state planning, the market
and Soviet democracy, can assure correct guidance of the economy
of the epoch of transition and assure, not the removal of the
imbalances in a few years (this is utopian), but their
diminution and by that the simplification of the bases of the
dictatorship the proletariat until the time when new victories
of the revolution will widen the arena of socialist planning and
reconstruct its system.” (Leon Trotsky: The Soviet Economy
in Danger. Available in French in Tome I of Ecrits
1928-1940, p.127). [In English, in a different
translation, see
The Soviet Economy in Danger in Militant,
12 November 1932-7 January 1933.]
7.
Certain Yugoslav authors take quite correct positions in this
respect. See, for example, Dr. Radivoj Uvalic: “While the open
market can be widely utilized, it cannot be the sole or even the
principle regulator of the socio-economic relations of a
socialist country.” And again: “The importance of the planned
guidance of economic development under the conditions of
socialism lies first of all in the possibility that is offered
of considering profitability from the point of view of the
economy as a whole and not from the point of view of each
particular unit of the economy… This is the case in all branches
of high concentration of capital (?), such as the production of
the means of production and raw materials, which could be never
developed sufficiently on the basis of the accidental play of
the market, with the rate of profit as the sole stimulate.” (In:
Socialist Thought and Practice, No.6, pp.47 and
55) |